LITERATUUR



Bewustzijnsfilosofie.



@

Abbott, B.

(1995):
Natural language and thought: Thinking in English.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 23, pp. 49-55.

@

Abbott, B.

(2000):
Fodor and Lepore on meaning similarity and compositionality.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 97, pp. 454-6.

@

Abelson, R.

(1970):
A refutation of mind-body identity.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 18, pp. 85-90.

@

Ackermann, D. F.

(1983):
Wittgenstein, rules and origin--privacy.
In: ' Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research ', vol. 1, pp. 63-69.

@

Adam, A.

(2003):
Cyborgs in the Chinese room: Boundaries transgressed and boundaries blurred.
In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Adams, F.

(1979):
Properties, functionalism, and the identity theory.
In: ' Eidos ', vol. 1, pp. 153-79.

@

Adams, F.

(1991):
Causal contents.
In: B. McLaughlin (Ed.): 'Dretske and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Adams, F.

(1993):
Fodor's modal argument.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 6, pp. 41-56.

@

Adams, F.

(2001):
Empathy, neural imaging and the theory versus simulation debate.
In: ' Mind & Language ', vol. 16, pp. 368-392.

@

Adams, F.

(2002):
Mental representation.
In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind '.
Blackwell.

@

Adams, F.

(2003):
The informational turn in philosophy.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 13, pp. 471-501.

@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(1992):
`X' means X: Semantics Fodor-style.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 2, pp. 175-83.

@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(1993):
Fodorian semantics, pathologies, and "Block's problem".
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 3, pp. 97-104.

@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(1994):
`X' means X: Fodor/Warfield semantics.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp. 215-31.

@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(1997):
Fodor's asymmetric causal dependency theory and proximal projections.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 35, pp. 433-437.

@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(1997):
Rock beats scissors: Historicalism fights back.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 57, pp. 273-81.

@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(2001):
The bounds of cognition.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 14, pp. 43-64.

@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.; Fuller, G.

(1992):
Rules in programming languages and networks.
In: J. Dinsmore (Ed.): 'The Symbolic and Connectionist Paradigms: Closing the Gap '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Adams, F.; Drebushenko, D.; Fuller, G.; Stecker, R.

(1990):
Narrow content: Fodor's folly.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 5, pp. 213-29.

@

Adams, F.; Fuller, G.

(1992):
Names, contents, and causes.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 7, pp. 205-21.

@

Adams, W.

(2004):
Machine consciousness: Plausible idea or semantic distortion?.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 11, no. 9, pp. 46-56.

@

Addis, L.

(1995):
The ontology of emotion.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 33, pp. 261-78.

@

Addis, L.

(2000):
The simplicity of content.
In: ' Metaphysica ', vol. 1, no. 2, pp. 23-44.

@

Adler, J.

(2002):
Belief's Own Ethics.
MIT Press.

@

Adolphs, R.

(2004):
'Edison' & 'Russell': Definitions versus inventions in the analysis of emotion.
In: J. Fellous (Ed.): 'Who Needs Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Adshead, G.

(1999):
Psychopaths and other-regarding beliefs.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology ', vol. 99, pp. 41-44.

@

Agar, N.

(1993):
What do frogs really believe?.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 71, pp. 1-12.

@

Agar, N.

(2003):
Functionalism and personal identity.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 37, pp. 52-70.

@

Agre, P.

(1995):
Computation and embodied agency.
In: ' Informatica ', vol. 19, pp. 527-35.

@

Agre, P.

(2002):
The practical logic of computer work.
In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): 'Computationalism: New Directions '.
MIT Press.

@

Aizawa, K.

(1994):
Lloyd's dialectical theory of representation.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 9, pp. 1-24.

@

Aizawa, K.

(1994):
Representations without rules, connectionism, and the syntactic argument.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 101, pp. 465-92.

@

Aizawa, K.

(1997):
Explaining systematicity.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 12, pp. 115-36.

@

Aizawa, K.

(1997):
The role of the systematicity argument in classicism and connectionism.
In: S. O'Nuallain (Ed.): 'Two Sciences of Mind '.
John Benjamins.

@

Aizawa, K.

(1997):
Exhibiting verses explaining systematicity: A reply to Hadley and Hayward.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 7, pp. 39-55.

@

Aizawa, K.

(2002):
Cognitive architecture.
In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind '.
Blackwell.

@

Alanen, L.

(2003):
What are emotions about?.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 67, pp. 311-354.

@

Albritton, R.

(1985):
Freedom of the will and freedom of action.
In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association ', vol. 59, pp. 239-51.

@

Aldridge, V. C.

(1987):
Kripke on Wittgenstein on Regulation.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 62, pp. 375-384.

@

Aleksander, I.

(2003):
Neural depictions of "world" and "self": Bringing computational understanding into the Chinese room .
In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Aleksander, I.; Dunmall, B.

(2003):
Axioms and tests for the presence of minimal consciousness in agents I: Preamble.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 10.

@

Alexander, P.

(1959):
Other people's experiences.
In: ' 1959 '.

@

Alexander, S.

(1920):
Space, Time, and Deity.
Macmillan.

@

Allen, A. H. B.

(1952):
Other minds.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 61, pp. 328-348.

@

Allen, B.

(1989):
Gruesome arithmetic: Kripke's sceptic replies.
In: ' Dialogue ', vol. 28, pp. 257-264.

@

Allen, C.

(1992):
Mental content.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 43, pp. 537-53.

@

Allen, C.

(1995):
It isn't what you think: A new idea about intentional causation.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 29, pp. 115-26.

@

Allen, C.

(1997):
Animal cognition and animal minds.
In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind '.
Pittsburgh University Press.

@

Allen, C.

(1999):
Animal concepts revisited: the use of self-monitoring as an empirical approach.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 51, pp. 537-544.

@

Allen, C.

(2004):
Is anyone a cognitive ethologist?.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 19, pp. 589-607.

@

Allen, C.; Bekoff, M.

(1992):
On aims and methods of cognitive ethology.
In: ' Philosophy of Science Association ', vol. 1992.

@

Allen, C.; Bekoff, M.

(1995):
Cognitive ethology and the intentionality of animal behavior.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 10, pp. 313-328.

@

Allen, C.; Bekoff, M.

(1997):
Species of Mind: The Philosophy and Biology of Cognitive Ethology.
MIT Press.

@

Allen, C.; Hauser, M.

(1991):
Concept attribution in nonhuman animals: Theoretical and methodological problems in ascribing complex mental processes .
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 58, pp. 221-40.

@

Almeida, M.; Bernstein, M.

(2003):
Lucky libertarianism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 22, pp. 93-119.

@

Almog, J.

(2001):
What Am I?: Descartes and the Mind-Body Problem.
Oxford University Press.

@

Alper, G.

(1990):
A psychoanalyst takes the Turing test.
In: ' Psychoanalytic Review ', vol. 77, pp. 59-68.

@

Alston, W. P.

(1971):
Varieties of priveleged access.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 8, pp. 223-41.

@

Alston, W. P.

(1983):
What's wrong with immediate knowledge?.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 55, pp. 73-96.

@

Alter, T.; Rachels, S.

(2002):
Epistemicism and the combined spectrum.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 17, pp. 241-55.

@

Ameriks, K.

(1973):
Plantinga and other minds.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 16, pp. 285-91.

@

Anderson, D.

(1987):
Is the Chinese room the real thing?.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 62, pp. 389-93.

@

Anderson, J. R.

(1978):
Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery.
In: ' Psychological Review ', vol. 85.

@

Andler, D.

(1995):
Can we knock off the shackles of syntax?.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Content '.
Ridgeview.

@

Andrews, K.

(2002):
Knowing mental states: The asymmetry of psychological prediction and explanation.
In: Q. Smith; A. Jokic (Ed.): 'Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Angel, L.

(1989):
How to Build a Conscious Machine.
Westview Press.

@

Angel, L.

(1994):
Am I a computer?.
In: E. Dietrich (Ed.): 'Thinking Computers and Virtual Persons '.
Academic Press.

@

Anscombe, G. E. M.

(1971):
Causality and Determinism.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Anscombe, G. E. M.

(1976):
`Soft' determinism.
In: G. Ryle (Ed.): 'Contemporary Aspects of Philosophy '.
Oriel Press.

@

Anscombe, G. E. M.

(1985):
Review of Saul Kripke's Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language.
In: ' Ethics ', vol. 95, pp. 342-352.

@

Anscombe, G. E. M.

(1985):
Critical Notice: Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 15, pp. 103-9.

@

Antony, L.

(1989):
Semantic anorexia: On the notion of content in cognitive science.
In: G. Boolos (Ed.): 'Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Antony, L.

(1989):
Anomalous monism and the problem of explanatory force.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 98, pp. 153-87.

@

Antony, L.

(1991):
The causal relevance of the mental.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 6, pp. 295-327.

@

Antony, L.

(1995):
Law and order in psychology.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 9, pp. 429-46.

@

Antony, L.

(1997):
Feeling fine about the mind.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 57, pp. 381-87.

@

Antony, L.

(1999):
Making room for the mental.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 95, pp. 37-44.

@

Antony, L.

(2001):
Brain states with attitude.
In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Explaining Beliefs '.
CSLI.

@

Antony, L.

(2001):
Empty heads?.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 16, pp. 193-214.

@

Antony, L. M.

(1999):
Multiple realizability, projectibility, and the reality of mental properties.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 26, pp. 1-24.

@

Antony, L. M.

(2003):
Who's afraid of disjunctive properties?.
In: ' Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp. 1-21.

@

Antony, L. M.; Levine, J.

(1997):
Reduction with autonomy.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 11, pp. 83-105.

@

Antony, L.; Levine, J.

(1991):
The nomic and the robust.
In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Antony, M. V.

(1991):
Fodor and Pylyshyn on connectionism.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp. 321-41.

@

Antony, M. V.

(1993):
Social relations and the individuation of thought.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 102, pp. 247-61.

@

Antony, M. V.

(2003):
Davidson's argument for monism.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 135, pp. 1-12.

@

Appelbaum, I.

(1998):
Fodor, modularity, and speech perception.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 11, pp. 317-330.

@

Apter, A.

(1991):
The problem of who: Multiple personality, personal identity, and the double brain.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 4, pp. 219-48.

@

Arbib, M.

(1989):
Modularity, schemas and neurons: A critique of Fodor.
In: P. Slezak (Ed.): 'Computers, Brains and Minds '.
Kluwer.

@

Arbib, M.

(2004):
Beware the passionate robot.
In: J. Fellous (Ed.): 'Who Needs Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Arcaya, J. M.

(1989):
Memory and temporality: A phenomenological alternative.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 2, pp. 101-110.

@

Ariew, A.

(1996):
Innateness and canalization.
In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement ', vol. 63, pp. 19-27.

@

Ariew, A.

(2002):
Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and Biology.
Oxford University Press.

@

Ariew, A.

(2003):
Natural selection doesn't work that way: Jerry Fodor vs. evolutionary psychology on gradualism and saltationism .
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 18, pp. 478-483.

@

Arjo, D.

(1996):
Sticking up for Oedipus: Fodor on intentional generalizations and broad content.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp. 231-45.

@

Arkway, A.

(2000):
The simulation theory, the theory theory and folk psychological explanation.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 98, pp. 115-137.

@

Arlo Costa, H.; Collins, J.; Levi, I.

(1995):
Desire-as-belief implies opinionation or indifference.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 55, pp. 2-5.

@

Armstrong, B.

(1984):
Wittgenstein on private languages: It takes two to talk.
In: ' Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 7.

@

Armstrong, D.

(1999):
The Mind-Body Problem: An Opinionated Introduction.
Westview Press.

@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1968):
A Materialist Theory of the Mind.
Routledge and Kegan Paul.

@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1968):
The headless woman and the defense of materialism.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 29, pp. 48-49.

@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1969):
Colour realism and the argument from microscopes.
In: R. Brown; C. Rollins (Ed.): 'Contemporary Philosophy in Australia '.
Humanities Press.

@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1970):
The nature of mind.
In: C. Borst (Ed.): 'The Mind/Brain Identity Theory '.
Macmillan.

@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1973):
Epistemological foundations for a materialist theory of mind.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 40, pp. 178-93.

@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1982):
Metaphysics and supervenience.
In: ' Critica ', vol. 42, pp. 3-17.

@

Armstrong, D. M.; Malcolm, N.

(1984):
Consciousness and Causality: A Debate on the Nature of Mind.
Blackwell.

@

Arregui, J. V.

(1996):
On the intentionality of moods: Phenomenology and linguistic analysis.
In: ' American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 70, pp. 397-411.

@

Arrington, R.

(1999):
Machines, consciousness, and thought.
In: ' Idealistic Studies ', vol. 29, pp. 231-243.

@

Arstila, V.

(2003):
True colors, false theories.
In: ' Australian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 81, pp. 41-61.

@

Atherton, M.; Schwarz, R.

(1974):
Linguistic innateness and its evidence.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 71.

@

Atkin A.

(1992):
On consciousness: What is the role of emergence?.
In: ' Medical Hypotheses ', vol. 38, pp. 311-14.

@

Atkinson, A. P.; Wheeler, M.

(2003):
Evolutionary psychology's grain problem and the cognitive neuroscience of reasoning.
In: D. Over (Ed.): 'Evolution and the Psychology of Thinking: The Debate '.
Psychology Press.

@

Atkinson, A. P.; Wheeler, M.

(2004):
The grain of domains: The evolutionary-psychological case against domain-general cognition.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 19, pp. 147-76.

@

Atkinson, A.; Wheeler, M.

(2004):
The grain of domains: The evolutionary-psychological case against domain-general cognition.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 19, pp. 147-176.

@

Atran, S.

(2005):
Adaptationism for human cognition: Strong, spurious, or weak?.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 20, pp. 39-67.

@

Audi, R.

(1974):
Moral responsibility, freedom, and compulsion.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 11, pp. 1-14.

@

Audi, R.

(1978):
The ontological status of mental images.
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 21, pp. 348-61.

@

Audi, R.

(1993):
Mental causation: Sustaining and dynamic.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Audi, R.

(1994):
Dispositional beliefs and dispositions to believe.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 28, pp. 419-34.

@

Aune, B.

(1961):
The problem of other minds.
In: ' 1961 '.

@

Aune, B.

(1966):
Feigl on the mind-body problem.
In: P. Feyerabend; G. Maxwell (Ed.): 'Mind, Matter, and Method: Essays in Philosophy and Science in Honor of Herbert Feigl '.
University of Minnesota Press.

@

Aune, B.

(1970):
Free will, 'can', and ethics: A reply to Lehrer.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 30, pp. 77-83.

@

Aune, B.

(1986):
Other minds after twenty years.
In: ' 1986 '.

@

Aune, B.

(1994):
Speaking of selves.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 44, pp. 279-93.

@

Austin, J.

(1946):
Other minds.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 20, pp. 148-87.

@

Austin, J. W.

(1975):
Rorty's materialism.
In: ' Auslegung ', vol. 3, pp. 20-28.

@

Averill, E. W.

(1985):
Color and the anthropocentric problem.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 82, pp. 281-303.

@

Averill, E. W.

(1992):
The relational nature of color.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 101, pp. 551-88.

@

Averill, E. W.; Keating, B.

(1981):
Does interactionism violate a law of classical physics?.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 90, pp. 102-7.

@

Avison, M. J.

(2002):
Functional brain mapping: What is it good for? Absolutely nothing.
In: ' Brain and Mind ', vol. 3, pp. 367-73.

@

Avramides, A.

(2001):
Other Minds.
Routledge.

@

Aydede, M.

(1997):
Has Fodor really changed his mind on narrow content?.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 12, pp. 422-58.

@

Aydede, M.

(1997):
Language of thought: The connectionist contribution.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 7, pp. 57-101.

@

Aydede, M.

(2000):
On the type/token relation of mental representations.
In: ' Facta Philosophica ', vol. 2, pp. 23-50.

@

Aydede, M.

(2000):
An analysis of pleasure vis-a-vis pain.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 61, pp. 537-570.

@

Aydede, M.

(2001):
Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism about pain.
In: ' Consciousness and Emotion ', vol. 2, pp. 29-73.

@

Aydede, M.

(2005):
Pain: New Essays on its Nature and the Methodology of its Study.
MIT Press.

@

Aydede, M.

(2005):
A critical and quasi-historical essay on theories of pain.
In: M. Aydede (Ed.): 'Pain: New Essays on its Nature and the Methodology of its Study '.
MIT Press.

@

Aydede, M.; Guzeldere, G.

(2002):
Some foundational problems in the scientific study of pain.
In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement ', vol. 69, pp. 265-83.

@

Aydede, M.; Robbins, P.

(2001):
Are Frege cases exceptions to intentional generalizations?.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 31, pp. 1-22.

@

Ayer, A.

(1960):
Professor Malcolm on dreams.
In: ' 1960 '.

@

Ayer, A. J.

(1953):
One's knowledge of other minds.
In: ' 1953 '.

@

Ayer, A. J.

(1954):
Can there be a private language?.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 27.

@

Ayer, A. J.

(1954):
Freedom and necessity.
In: ' Philosophical Essays '.

@

Ayer, A. J.

(1956):
The Problem of Knowledge.
Harmondsworth.

@

Ayer, A. J.

(1980):
Free will and rationality.
In: Z. van Straaten (Ed.): 'Philosophical Subjects '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Ayers, M.

(1968):
The Refutation of Determinism.
Methuen.

@

Bacon, J.

(1986):
Supervenience, necessary coextensions, and reducibility.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 49, pp. 163-76.

@

Bacon, J.

(1995):
Weak supervenience supervenes.
In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Badcock, C.

(2004):
Emotion verses reason as a genetic conflict.
In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): 'Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Baier, A.

(1976):
Mixing memory and desire.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 13, pp. 213-20.

@

Baier, A.

(1990):
What emotions are about.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 4, pp. 1-29.

@

Baier, A.

(2004):
Feelings that matter.
In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Baier, K.

(1962):
Smart on sensations.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 40, pp. 57-68.

@

Bailey, A.

(1998):
Supervenience and physicalism.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 117, pp. 53-73.

@

Baillie, J.

(1991):
Split brains and single minds.
In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research ', vol. 16, pp. 11-18.

@

Baillie, J.

(1993):
Recent work on personal identity.
In: ' Philosophical Books ', vol. 34, pp. 193-206.

@

Baillie, J.

(1993):
What matters in survival.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 31, pp. 255-61.

@

Baillie, J.

(1996):
Identity, relation R, and what matters: A challenge to Derek Parfit.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 77, pp. 263-267.

@

Baillie, J.

(1997):
Personal identity and mental content.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 10, pp. 323-33.

@

Bain, D.

(2003):
Intentionalism and pain.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 53, pp. 502-523.

@

Baker, G. P.; Hacker, P. M. S.

(1984):
Scepticism, Rules and Language.
Blackwell.

@

Baker, G. P.; Hacker, P. M. S.

(1985):
Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity.

@

Baker, G.; Hacker, P.

(1984):
Critical study: On misunderstanding Wittgenstein: Kripke's private language argument.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 58.

@

Baker, G.; Hacker, P.

(1986):
Reply to Mr. Mounce.
In: ' Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 9, pp. 199-204.

@

Baker, G.; and Hacker, P.

(1990):
Malcolm on language and rules.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 65, pp. 167-179.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1985):
A farewell to functionalism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 48, pp. 1-14.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1985):
Just what do we have in mind?.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 10, pp. 25-48.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1986):
Content by courtesy.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 84, pp. 197-213.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1987):
Instrumentalism: Back from the brink?.
In: ' Saving Belief '.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1987):
The threat of cognitive suicide.
In: ' Saving Belief '.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1987):
Saving Belief.
Princeton University Press.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1987):
Saving Belief.
Princeton University Press.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1988):
Cognitive suicide.
In: R. Grimm; D. Merrill (Ed.): 'Contents of Thought '.
University of Arizona Press.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1989):
Instrumental intentionality.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 56, pp. 303-16.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1989):
Recent work in the philosophy of mind.
In: ' Philosophical Books ', vol. 30, pp. 1-9.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1990):
On a causal theory of content.
In: ' 1990 '.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1991):
Has content been naturalized?.
In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1991):
Dretske on the explanatory role of belief.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 63, pp. 99-111.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1993):
What beliefs are not.
In: S. Wagner; R. Warner (Ed.): 'Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal '.
University of Notre Dame Press.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1993):
Metaphysics and mental causation.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1994):
Attitudes as nonentities.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 76, pp. 175-203.

@

Baker, L. R.

(1994):
Content and context.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 8, pp. 17-32.

@

Baker, L. R.

(2000):
Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Baker, L. R.

(2001):
Are beliefs brain states?.
In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Explaining Beliefs '.
CSLI.

@

Baker, L. R.

(2001):
Practical realism defended: Replies to critics.
In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Explaining Beliefs '.
CSLI.

@

Balaguer, M.

(1998):
Attitudes without propositions.
In: ' Philosophy and phenomenological research ', vol. 58, pp. 805-26.

@

Balaguer, M.

(1999):
Libertarianism as a scientifically respectable view.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 93, pp. 189-211.

@

Balaguer, M.

(2002):
A coherent, naturalistic, and plausible formulation of libertarian free will.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 38, pp. 379-406.

@

Baldwin, M.

(1998):
Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology.
Westview.

@

Ballard, D.

(1991):
Animate vision.
In: ' Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 48, pp. 57-86.

@

Bar-On, D.

(1992):
On the possibility of a solitary language.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 26, pp. 27-46.

@

Bar-On, D.

(2000):
Speaking my mind.
In: ' Philsophical topics ', vol. 28, pp. 1-34.

@

Bar-On, D.

(2004):
Externalism and self-knowledge: Content, use, and expression.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 38, pp. 430-55.

@

Bar-On, D.

(2004):
Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge.
Oxford University Press.

@

Bar-On, D.; Long, D.

(2001):
Avowals and first-person privilege.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 52, pp. 311-35.

@

Bar-On, D.; Long, D.

(2003):
Expressing truths and knowing truths.
In: B. Gertler (Ed.): 'Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self-Knowledge '.
Ashgate.

@

Barber, A.

(1998):
The pleonasticity of talk about concepts.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 89, pp. 53-86.

@

Barkin, E.

(2003):
Relative phenomenalism: Toward a more plausible theory of mind.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 10, no. 8, pp. 3-13.

@

Barkow, J.; Cosmides, L.; Tooby, J.

(1992):
The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture.
Oxford University Press.

@

Barnes, E.

(1991):
The causal history of computational activity: Maudlin and Olympia.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 88, pp. 304-16.

@

Baron-Cohen, S.; Tager-Flusberg, H.; Cohen, D. J.

(1994):
Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives from Autism.
Oxford University Press.

@

Barresi, J.

(1987):
Prospects for the Cyberiad: Certain limits on human self-knowledge in the cybernetic age.
In: ' Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior ', vol. 17, pp. 19-46.

@

Barresi, J.

(1999):
On becoming a person.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 12, pp. 79-98.

@

Barrett, H. C.

(2005):
Enzymatic computation and cognitive modularity.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 20, pp. 259-87.

@

Barrett, J.

(1994):
Rationalizing explanation and causally relevant mental properties.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 74, pp. 77-102.

@

Barrett, J.

(1995):
Causal relevance and nonreductive physicalism.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 42, pp. 339-62.

@

Barrett, J.

(1997):
Individualism and the cross-contexts test.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 78, pp. 242-60.

@

Barwise, J.

(1986):
Information and circumstance.
In: ' 1986 '.

@

Barwise, J.

(1987):
Unburdening the language of thought.
In: ' 1987 '.

@

Barwise, J.; Perry, J.

(1983):
Situations and Attitudes.
MIT Press.

@

Bateson, P. P. G.; Klopfer, P. H.

(1991):
Perspectives in Ethology, Volume 9: Human Understanding and Animal Awareness.
Plenum Press.

@

Batitsky, V.

(1998):
A formal rebuttal of the central argument for fnuctionalism.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 49, pp. 201-20.

@

Bayne, T.; Pacherie, E.

(2004):
Bottom-up or top-down: Campbell's rationalist account of monothematic delusions.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, ', vol. 11.

@

Bayne, T.; Pacherie, E.

(2005):
In defence of the doxastic conception of delusions.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 20, pp. 163-88.

@

Bealer, G.

(1978):
An inconsistency in functionalism.
In: ' 1978 '.

@

Bealer, G.

(1985):
Mind and anti-mind: Why thinking has no functional definition.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 9, pp. 283-328.

@

Bealer, G.

(1986):
The logical status of mind.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 10.

@

Bealer, G.

(1987):
The boundary between philosophy and cognitive science.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 86, pp. 553-55.

@

Bealer, G.

(1997):
Self-consciousness.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 106, pp. 69-117.

@

Bealer, G.

(2001):
The self-consciousness argument: Why Tooley's criticisms fail.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 105, pp. 281-307.

@

Beardman, S.

(2000):
The choice between current and retrospective evaluations of pain. 13:97-110. :dez, J. L. 2001: Normativity and rationality in delusional psychiatric disorders .
In: ' Mind & Language, ', vol. 16.

@

Beauregard, M.

(2004):
Consciousness, Emotional Self-Regulation and the Brain.
John Benjamins.

@

Beavers, A. F.

(2002):
Phenomenology and artificial intelligence.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 33, pp. 70-82.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1983):
A bridge between cognitive science and neuroscience: The functional architecture of mind.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 44, pp. 319-30.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1984):
Autonomous psychology: What it should and should not entail.
In: ' Philosophy of Science Association ', vol. 1984.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1985):
Realism, instrumentalism, and the intentional stance.
In: ' Cognitive Science ', vol. 9, pp. 265-92.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1985):
Are the new PDP models of cognition cognitivist or associationist?.
In: ' Behaviorism ', vol. 13, pp. 53-61.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1986):
What happens to accounts of mind-brain relations if we forgo an architecture of rules and representations? .
In: ' Philosophy of Science Association ', vol. 1986.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1987):
Connectionism and the philosophy of mind.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement ', vol. 26, pp. 17-41.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1988):
Connectionism and rules and representation systems: Are they compatible?.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 1, pp. 5-16.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1988):
Philosophy of Mind: An Overview for Cognitive Science.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1993):
The case for connectionism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 71, pp. 119-54.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1994):
Levels of description and explanation in cognitive science.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp. 1-25.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1996):
Yet another revolution: Defusing the dynamical system theorists' attack on mental representations.

@

Bechtel, W.

(1996):
Yet another revolution? Defusing the dynamical system theorists' attack on mental representations.

@

Bechtel, W.

(2001):
Cognitive neuroscienec: Relating neural mechanisms and cognition.
In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences '.
University of Pittsburgh Press.

@

Bechtel, W.

(2001):
Decomposing and localizing vision: An exemplar for cognitive neuroscience.
In: W. Bechtel; P. Mandik; J. Mundale; and R. Stufflebeam (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader '.
Blackwell.

@

Bechtel, W.

(2002):
Decomposing the mind-brain: A long-term pursuit.
In: ' Brain and Mind ', vol. 3, pp. 229-42.

@

Bechtel, W.

(2002):
Aligning multiple research techniques in cognitive neuroscience: Why is it important?.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 69, pp. 548-558.

@

Bechtel, W.; Abrahamsen, A. A.

(1992):
Connectionism and the future of folk psychology.
In: R. Burton (Ed.): 'Minds: Natural and Artificial '.
SUNY Press.

@

Bechtel, W.; Abrahamson, A.

(1990):
Beyond the exclusively propositional era.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 82, pp. 223-53.

@

Bechtel, W.; Mandik, P.; Mundale, J.; and Stufflebeam, R. S.

(2001):
Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader.
Blackwell.

@

Bechtel, W.; Mundale, J.

(1999):
Multiple realizability revisited: Linking cognitive and neural states.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 66, pp. 175-207.

@

Bechtel, W.; Stufflebeam, R.

(2001):
Epistemic issues in procuring evidence about the brain: The importance of research instruments and techniques .
In: W. Bechtel; P. Mandik; J. Mundale; and R. Stufflebeam (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader '.
Blackwell.

@

Beck, S.

(1989):
Parfit and the Russians (personal identity and moral concepts).
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 49, pp. 205-209.

@

Beck, S.

(2001):
Let's exist again (like we did last Summer).
In: ' South African Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 20, pp. 159-170.

@

Becker, K.

(1998):
On the perfectly general nature of instability in meaning holism.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 95, pp. 635-640.

@

Beckerman, A.

(2001):
The real reason for the standard view.
In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Explaining Beliefs '.
CSLI.

@

Beckermann, A, Flohr, H.; Kim, J.

(1992):
Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism.
De Gruyter.

@

Beckermann, A, Flohr, H.; Kim, J.

(1992):
Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism.
De Gruyter.

@

Beckermann, A.

(1992):
Reductive and nonreductive physicalism.
In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism '.
De Gruyter.

@

Beckermann, A.

(1992):
Supervenience, emergence, and reduction.
In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism '.
De Gruyter.

@

Beckermann, A.

(1996):
Is there a problem about intentionality?.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 45, pp. 1-24.

@

Beckermann, A.

(1997):
Property physicalism, reduction, and realization.
In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind '.
Pittsburgh University Press.

@

Beckermann, A.

(2001):
Physicalism and new wave reductionism.
In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien ', vol. 61, pp. 257-261.

@

Bedau, M.

(1997):
Weak emergence.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 11, pp. 375-399.

@

Bedford, E.

(1957):
Emotions.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 57, pp. 281-304.

@

Beebee, H.

(2002):
Transfer of warrant, begging the question, and semantic externalism.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 51, pp. 356-74.

@

Beer, C. G.

(1992):
Conceptual issues in cognitive ethology.
In: ' Advances in the Study of Behavior ', vol. 21, pp. 69-109.

@

Beer, R.

(1995):
A dynamical systems perspective on agent-environment interaction.
In: ' Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 72, pp. 173-215.

@

Bekoff, M.

(1999):
Social cognition: Exchanging and sharing information on the run.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 51, pp. 617-632.

@

Bekoff, M.; Jamieson, D.

(1996):
Readings in Animal Cognition.
MIT Press.

@

Beloff, J.

(1965):
The identity hypothesis: A critique.
In: J. R. Smythies (Ed.): 'Brain and Mind '.
Routledge and Kegan Paul.

@

Ben-Yami, H.

(1993):
A note on the Chinese room.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 95, pp. 169-72.

@

Ben-Yami, H.

(1997):
Against characterizing mental states as propositional attitudes.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 186, pp. 84-89.

@

Ben-Yami, H.

(1999):
An argument against functionalism.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 77, pp. 320-324.

@

Ben-Ze'ev, A.

(1987):
The nature of emotions.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 52, pp. 393-409.

@

Ben-Ze'ev, A.

(1990):
Describing the emotions.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 3, pp. 305-17.

@

Ben-Ze'ev, A.

(1992):
Emotional and moral evaluations.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 23, pp. 214-29.

@

Ben-Ze'ev, A.

(2003):
The logic of emotions.
In: A. Hatimoysis (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Emotions '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Ben-Ze'ev, A.

(2004):
Emotion as a subtle mental mode.
In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Ben-Zeev, A.

(1986):
Two approaches to memory.
In: ' Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 9, pp. 288-301.

@

Benacerraf, P.

(1967):
God, the Devil, and Godel.
In: ' Monist ', vol. 51, pp. 9-32.

@

Benejam, A.

(2003):
Thought experiments and semantic competence.
In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind '.
CSLI.

@

Benn, S.

(1988):
A Theory of Freedom.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Benner, D. G.; Evans, C. S.

(1984):
Unity and multiplicity in hypnosis, commissurotomy, and multiple personality disorder.
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 5, pp. 423-431.

@

Bennett, J.

(1991):
Analysis without noise.
In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): 'Mind and Common Sense '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Bennett, J.

(1991):
Folk-psychological explanations.
In: J. Greenwood (Ed.): 'The Future of Folk Psychology '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Bennett, K.

(2003):
Why the exclusion problem seems intractable and how, just maybe, to tract it.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 37, pp. 471-97.

@

Bennett, K.

(2004):
Global supervenience and dependence.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 68, pp. 501-529.

@

Bennett, L. J.

(1990):
Modularity of mind revisited.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 41, pp. 429-36.

@

Benson, S.

(1987):
Freedom and value.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 84, pp. 465-87.

@

Benson, S.

(1994):
Free agency and self-worth.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 91, pp. 650-58.

@

Benstein, M.

(1992):
Fatalism.
University of Nebraska Press.

@

Bentall, R.

(2003):
Madness Explained.
Allen Lane.

@

Berenda, C. W.

(1953):
On emergence and prediction.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 50, pp. 269-74.

@

Berg, J.

(1998):
First-person authority, externalism, and wh-knowledge.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 52, pp. 41-44.

@

Bergadano, F.

(1993):
Machine learning and the foundations of inductive inference.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 3, pp. 31-51.

@

Bergmann, F.

(1977):
On Being Free.
University of Notre Dame Press.

@

Bergmann, G.

(1944):
Holism, historicism, and emergence.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 11, pp. 209-21.

@

Bergson, H.

(1991):
Matter and memory.
In: ' 1991 '.

@

Bergstrom, C.; Godfrey-Smith, P.

(1998):
On the evolution of behavioral complexity in individuals and populations.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 13, pp. 205-31.

@

Berkeley, I.

(2000):
What the #$%! is a subsymbol?.
In: ' Minds and machines ', vol. 10, pp. 1-14.

@

Bermudez, J.

(2002):
Rationality and psychological explanation without language.
In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature '.
Clarendon.

@

Bermudez, J.

(2005):
Philosophy of Psychology.
Routledge.

@

Bermudez, J. L.

(1999):
Naturalism and conceptual norms.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 49, pp. 77-85.

@

Bermudez, J. L.

(2001):
Normativity and rationality in delusional psychiatric disorders.
In: ' Mind & Language, ', vol. 16.

@

Bermudez, J. L.

(2003):
The elusiveness thesis, immunity to error through misidentification, and privileged access.
In: B. Gertler (Ed.): 'Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self-Knowledge '.
Ashgate.

@

Bermudez, J. L.

(2003):
The domain of folk psychology.
In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Minds and Persons '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Bermudez, J. L.

(2003):
Thinking Without Words.
Oxford University Press.

@

Bermudez, J. L.

(2003):
Ascribing thoughts to non-linguistic creatures.
In: ' Facta Philosophica ', vol. 5, pp. 313-34.

@

Bermudez, J. L.; Marcel, A.; Eilan, N.

(1995):
The Body and the Self.
MIT Press.

@

Bernecker, S.

(1996):
Davidson on first-person authority and externalism.
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 39, pp. 121-39.

@

Bernecker, S.

(1996):
Externalism and the attitudinal component of self-knowledge.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 30, pp. 262-75.

@

Bernecker, S.

(1998):
Self-knowledge and closure.
In: P. Ludlow; N. Martin (Ed.): 'Externalism and Self-Knowledge '.
CSLI.

@

Bernecker, S.

(2004):
Memory and externalism.
In: ' Philosophical and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 69.

@

Bernier, P.

(1993):
Narrow content, context of thought, and asymmetric dependence.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 8, pp. 327-42.

@

Bernier, P.

(2002):
From simulation to theory. In (J. Dokic & J.
In: ' 2002 '.

@

Bernstein, M.

(1995):
Kanean libertarianism.
In: ' Southwest Philosophical Review ', vol. 11, pp. 151-57.

@

Bernstein, M.

(2002):
Fatalism.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Bernstein, R.

(1968):
The challenge of scientific materialism.
In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 8, pp. 252-75.

@

Berofsky, B.

(1966):
Free Will and Determinism.
Harper and Row.

@

Berofsky, B.

(1971):
Determinism.
Princeton University Press.

@

Berofsky, B.

(1987):
Freedom from Necessity: The Metaphysical Basis of Responsibility.
Routledge.

@

Berofsky, B.

(2000):
Ultimate rsponsibility in a determined world.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 60, pp. 135-40.

@

Berofsky, B.

(2002):
Ifs, cans, and free will: The issues.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Berrios, G.

(1991):
Delusions as 'wrong beliefs': A conceptual history.
In: ' British Journal of Psychiatry, ', vol. 159.

@

Bertocci, P. A.

(1978):
The essence of a person.
In: ' Monist ', vol. 61, pp. 28-41.

@

Bertolet, R.

(1994):
Saving eliminativism.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 7, pp. 87-100.

@

Bestor, T. W.

(1979):
Gilbert Ryle and the adverbial theory of mind.
In: ' Personalist ', vol. 60, pp. 233-42.

@

Bestor, T. W.

(1991):
Naturalizing semantics: New insights or old folly?.
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 34, pp. 285-310.

@

Bickhard, M.

(1993):
Representational content in humans and machines.
In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 5, pp. 285-33.

@

Bickhard, M.

(1996):
Troubles with computationalism.
In: W. O'Donahue; R. Kitchener (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of Psychology '.
Sage Publications.

@

Bickhard, M. H.

(2004):
The dynamic emergence of representation.
In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Representation in Mind '.
Elsevier.

@

Bickle, J.

(1992):
Revisionary physicalism.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 7, pp. 411-30.

@

Bickle, J.

(1992):
Multiple realizability and psychophysical reduction.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 20, pp. 47-58.

@

Bickle, J.

(1992):
Mental anomaly and the new mind-brain reductionism.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 59, pp. 217-30.

@

Bickle, J.

(1993):
Connectionism, eliminativism, and the semantic view of theories.
In: ' 1993 '.

@

Bickle, J.

(1995):
Connectionism, reduction, and multiple realizability.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 23, pp. 29-39.

@

Bickle, J.

(1995):
Psychoneural reduction of the genuinely cognitive: Some accomplished facts.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 8, pp. 265-85.

@

Bickle, J.

(1995):
Connectionism, reduction, and multiple realizability.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 23, pp. 29-39.

@

Bickle, J.

(1996):
New wave psychophysical reductionism and the methodological caveats.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 56, pp. 57-78.

@

Bickle, J.

(1997):
Psychoneural Reductionism: The New Wave.
MIT Press.

@

Bickle, J.

(2001):
New wave metascience: Replies to Beckermann, Maloney, and Stephan.
In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien ', vol. 61, pp. 285-293.

@

Bickle, J.

(2002):
Philosophy of mind and the sciences.
In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind '.
Blackwell.

@

Bigelow, J. Collins, J.; Pargetter, R.

(1990):
Colouring in the world.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 99, pp. 279-88.

@

Bilgrami, A.

(1987):
An externalist account of psychological content.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 15, pp. 191-226.

@

Bilgrami, A.

(1989):
Realism without internalism: A critique of Searle on intentionality.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 86, pp. 57-72.

@

Bilgrami, A.

(1992):
Can externalism be reconciled with self-knowledge?.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 20, pp. 233-68.

@

Bilgrami, A.

(1992):
Belief and Meaning: The Unity and Locality of Mental Content.
Blackwell.

@

Bilgrami, A.

(1993):
Norms and meaning.
In: R. Stoecker (Ed.): 'Reflecting Davidson '.
de Gruyter.

@

Bilgrami, A.

(1994):
Other minds.
In: J. Dancy; E. Sosa (Ed.): 'A Companion to Epistemology '.
Blackwell.

@

Bilgrami, A.

(1998):
Why holism is harmless and necessary.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 12, pp. 105-126.

@

Bilgrami, A.

(2000):
Self-knowledge and resentment.
In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Bilgrami, A.

(2003):
A trilemma for redeployment.
In: ' Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp. 22-30.

@

Birnbacher, D.

(1995):
Artificial consciousness.
In: T. Metzinger (Ed.): 'Conscious Experience '.
Ferdinand Schoningh.

@

Birnbaum, L.

(1991):
Rigor mortis: A response to Nilsson's `Logic and artificial intelligence'.
In: ' Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 47, pp. 57-78.

@

Biro, J. I.

(1981):
Persons as corporate entities and corporations as persons.
In: ' Nature and System ', vol. 3, pp. 173-80.

@

Biro, J. I.

(1992):
In defense of social content.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 67, pp. 277-93.

@

Biro, J. I.; Shahan, R. W.

(1982):
Mind, Brain and Function.
Oklahoma University Press.

@

Biro, J.; Ludwig, K.

(1994):
Are there more than minimal a priori limits on irrationality?.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 72, pp. 89-102.

@

Bishop, J.

(1983):
Agent-causation.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 92, pp. 61-79.

@

Bishop, J.

(1986):
Is agent-causality a conceptal primitive?.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 67, pp. 225-47.

@

Bishop, J.

(1993):
Compatibilism and the free will defense.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 71, pp. 104-20.

@

Bishop, M.

(2002):
Counterfactuals cannot count: A rejoinder to David Chalmers.
In: ' Consciousness and Cognition ', vol. 11, pp. 642-52.

@

Bishop, M.

(2003):
Dancing with pixies: Strong artificial intelligence and panpsychism.
In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Bishop, M. A.

(2002):
The theory theory thrice over: The child as scientist, superscientist, or social institution?.
In: ' Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ', vol. 33, pp. 121-36.

@

Bishop, R. C.

(2002):
Chaos, indeterminism, and free will.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Blachowicz, J.

(1997):
Analog representation beyond mental imagery.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 94, pp. 55-84.

@

Blachowicz, J.

(1997):
Analog representation beyond mental imagery.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 94, pp. 55-84.

@

Blackburn, S.

(1984):
The individual strikes back.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 58.

@

Blackburn, S.

(1984):
Supervenience revisited.
In: I. Hacking (Ed.): 'Exercises in Analysis: Essays by Students of Casimir Lewy '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Blackburn, S.

(1991):
Losing your mind: Physics, identity, and folk burglar prevention.
In: J. Greenwood (Ed.): 'The Future of Folk Psychology '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Blackburn, S.

(1992):
Theory, observation, and drama.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 7.

@

Blackburn, S.

(1998):
Ruling Passions.
Oxford University Press.

@

Blackman, L. L.

(2002):
Mind as intentionality alone.
In: ' Metaphysica ', vol. 3, no. 2, pp. 41-64.

@

Block, N.

(1978):
Troubles with functionalism.
In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 9, pp. 261-325.

@

Block, N.

(1980):
Functionalism.
In: N. Block (Ed.): 'Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology '.
, Vol.

@

Block, N.

(1981):
Psychologism and behaviorism.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 90, pp. 5-43.

@

Block, N.

(1981):
Imagery.
MIT Press.

@

Block, N.

(1983):
Mental pictures and cognitive science.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 93, pp. 499-542.

@

Block, N.

(1983):
The photographic fallacy in the debate about mental imagery.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 17, pp. 651-62.

@

Block, N.

(1986):
Advertisement for a semantics for psychology.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 10, pp. 615-78.

@

Block, N.

(1988):
Functional role and truth conditions.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 61, pp. 157-181.

@

Block, N.

(1989):
Can the mind change the world?.
In: G. Boolos (Ed.): 'Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Block, N.

(1990):
The computer model of mind.
In: D. Osherson; E. Smith (Ed.): 'An Invitation to Cognitive Science '.
, Vol.

@

Block, N.

(1991):
What narrow content is not.
In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Block, N.

(1995):
Ruritania revisited.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Content '.
Ridgeview.

@

Block, N.

(1995):
An argument for holism.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 95, pp. 151-70.

@

Block, N.

(1995):
Reply: Causation and two kinds of laws.
In: C. Macdonald; G. Macdonald (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Psychology: Debates on Psychological Explanation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Block, N.

(1997):
Anti-reductionism slaps back.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 11, pp. 107-32.

@

Block, N.

(2003):
Do causal powers drain away.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 67, pp. 133-150.

@

Block, N.

(2003):
Searle's arguments against cognitive science.
In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Block, N.; Flanagan, O.; Guzeldere, G.

(1997):
The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates.
MIT Press.

@

Block, N.; Fodor, J. A.

(1972):
What psychological states are not.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 81, pp. 159-81.

@

Bloor, D.

(1997):
Wittgenstein, Rules and Institutions.
Routledge.

@

Blum, A.

(1991):
A note on pleasure.
In: ' Journal of Value Inquiry ', vol. 25, pp. 367-70.

@

Blumenfeld, D.

(1971):
The principle of alternate possibilities.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 67, pp. 339-44.

@

Blumenfeld, D.

(1988):
Freedom and mind control.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 25, pp. 215-27.

@

Blumenfeld, J-B.

(1979):
Phenomenal properties and the identity theory.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 63, pp. 485-93.

@

Blunt, P. K.

(1992):
A defense of folk psychology.
In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 32, pp. 487-98.

@

Bodansky, E.

(1987):
Parfit on selves and their interests.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 47, pp. 47-50.

@

Boden, M.

(1984):
What is computational psychology?.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 58, pp. 17-35.

@

Boden, M.

(1988):
Escaping from the Chinese Room.
In: ' Computer Models of Mind '.

@

Boden, M.

(2001):
The philosopgt of cognitive science.
In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Philosophy at the New Millenium '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Boden, M.

(2003):
The Creative Mind.
Routledge.

@

Boden, M. A.

(1994):
Multiple personality and computational models.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 37, pp. 103-114.

@

Boer, de, R.

(1976):
Cartesian categories in mind-body identity theories.
In: ' Philosophical Forum ', vol. 7, pp. 139-58.

@

Bogdan, R.

(1986):
Belief: Form, Content, and Function.
Oxford University Press.

@

Bogdan, R.

(2000):
Minding Minds: Evolving a Reflexive Mind by Interpreting Others.
MIT Press.

@

Bogdan, R. G.

(1991):
Mind and Common Sense: Philosophical Essays on Commonsense Psychology.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Bogdan, R. G.

(2003):
Minding Minds: Evolving a Reflexive Mind by Interpreting Others.
MIT Press.

@

Bogdan, R. J.

(1986):
The manufacture of belief.
In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): 'Belief: Form, Content, and Function '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Bogdan, R. J.

(1987):
Mind, content and information.
In: ' 1987 '.

@

Bogdan, R. J.

(1988):
Information and semantic cognition: An ontological account.
In: ' 1988 '.

@

Bogdan, R. J.

(1989):
Does semantics run the psyche?.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 49, pp. 687-700.

@

Bogen, J.

(2001):
Functional imaging evidence: Some epistemic hotspots.
In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences '.
University of Pittsburgh Press.

@

Boghossian, P,

(1992):
Externalism and inference.
In: ' Philosophical Issues ', vol. 2, pp. 11-28.

@

Boghossian, P.

(1989):
Content and self-knowledge.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 17, pp. 5-26.

@

Boghossian, P.

(1989):
The rule-following considerations.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 98, pp. 507-49.

@

Boghossian, P.

(1990):
The status of content.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 99, pp. 157-84.

@

Boghossian, P.

(1991):
Naturalizing content.
In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Boghossian, P.

(1991):
The status of content revisited.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 71, pp. 264-78.

@

Boghossian, P.

(1994):
The transparency of mental content.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 8, pp. 33-50.

@

Boghossian, P.

(1997):
What the externalist can know a priori.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 97, pp. 161-75.

@

Boghossian, P.

(2002):
Seeking the real.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 108, pp. 223-38.

@

Boghossian, P.

(2003):
The normativity of content.
In: ' Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp. 31-45.

@

Boghossian, P. A.

(1994):
Inferential-role semantics and the analytic/synthetic distinction.
In: ' 1994 '.

@

Boghossian, P.; Velleman, J. D.

(1989):
Color as a secondary quality.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 98, pp. 81-103.

@

Boghossian, P.; Velleman, J. D.

(1991):
Physicalist theories of color.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 100, pp. 67-106.

@

Bok, H.

(1998):
Freedom and Responsibility.
Princeton University Press.

@

Bolender, J.

(1995):
Is multiple realizability compatible with antireductionism?.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 33, pp. 129-42.

@

Bolender, J.

(2003):
A farewell to isms.
In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation '.
Imprint Academic.

@

BonJour, L.

(1976):
Deeterminism, libertarianism, and agent causation.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 14, pp. 145-56.

@

Bonevac, D.

(1988):
Supervenience and ontology.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 25, pp. 37-47.

@

Bonjour, L.

(1991):
Is thought a symbolic process?.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 89, pp. 331-52.

@

Bontly, T.

(2001):
Should intentionality be naturalized?.
In: D. Walsh (Ed.): 'Evolution, Naturalism and Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Bontly, T.

(2002):
The supervenience argument generalizes.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 109, pp. 75-96.

@

Bontly, T. D.

(2002):
The supervenience argument generalizes.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 109, pp. 75-96.

@

Borges, M.

(2004):
What can Kant teach us about emotions.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 101, pp. 140-158.

@

Borst, C. V.

(1970):
The Mind/Brain Identity Theory.
Macmillan.

@

Bortolotti, L.

(2005):
Delusions and the background of rationality.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 20, pp. 189-208.

@

Botterell, A.

(2002):
Physicalism, supervenience, and dependence: a reply to Campbell.
In: ' Dialogue ', vol. 41, pp. 155-161.

@

Botterill, G.

(1994):
Beliefs, functionally discrete states, and connectionist networks.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 45, pp. 899-906.

@

Botterill, G.

(1996):
Folk psychology and theoretical status.
In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Bovens, L.

(1994):
Principles of supervenience.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 72, pp. 294-301.

@

Bovens, L.

(1999):
Do beliefs supervene on degrees of confidence?.
In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Belief, Cognition, and the Will '.
Tilburg University Press.

@

Bowie, G.

(1982):
Lucas' number is finally up.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy Logic, ', vol. 11, pp. 279-85.

@

Bowman, A.

(1953):
Knowledge of other minds.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 50, pp. 328-32.

@

Boyd, R.

(1980):
Materialism without reductionism: What physicalism does not entail.
In: N. Block (Ed.): 'Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology '.
, Vol 1.

@

Boyd, R.

(1999):
Kinds, complexity, and multiple realization.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 95, pp. 67-98.

@

Boyer, D.

(1983):
J. R. Lucas, Kurt Godel, and Fred Astaire.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 33, pp. 147-59.

@

Boyle, C. F.

(1994):
Computation as an intrinsic property.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp. 451-67.

@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.

(2004):
Masters of our meanings.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 118, pp. 133-52.

@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.; Fitzpatrick, J.

(1990):
Explanation and the language of thought.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 83, pp. 3-29.

@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.; Jackson, F.

(1997):
The teleological theory of content.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 75, pp. 474-89.

@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.; Jackson, F.

(1997):
Philosophy of Mind and Cognition.
Blackwell.

@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.; Jackson, F.

(2002):
A pyrrhic victory for teleonomy.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 80, pp. 372-77.

@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.; Jackson, K.

(1999):
The divide-and-conquer path to analytic functionalism.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 26, pp. 71-89.

@

Bradley, M. C.

(1963):
Sensations, brain-processes, and colours.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 41, pp. 385-93.

@

Bradshaw, D. E.

(1991):
Connectionism and the specter of representationalism.
In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind '.
Kluwer.

@

Braithwaite, M.

(1949):
Causal laws in psychology.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 23, pp. 45-60.

@

Brakel, van, J.

(1991):
Meaning, prototypes, and the future of cognitive science.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp. 233-57.

@

Brakel, van, J.

(1996):
Interdiscourse or supervenience relations: The primacy of the manifest image.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 106, pp. 253-97.

@

Brakel, van, J.

(2005):
Supervenience and anomalous monism.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 53, pp. 3-24.

@

Brandom, R.

(1994):
Reasoning and representing.
In: M. Michael; J. O'Leary-Hawthorne (Ed.): 'Philosophy in Mind '.
Kluwer.

@

Brandom, R.

(1994):
Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment.
Harvard University Press.

@

Brandom, R.

(2001):
Modality, normativity, and intentionality.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 63, pp. 611-23.

@

Brandt, R.

(1960):
Doubts about the identity theory.
In: S. Hook (Ed.): 'Dimensions of Mind '.
New York University Press.

@

Brandt, R.; Kim, J.

(1967):
The logic of the identity theory.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 66, pp. 515-537.

@

Bratman, M.

(1990):
Dretske's desires.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 50, pp. 795-800.

@

Bratman, M.

(2003):
A desire of one's own.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 100, pp. 221-42.

@

Braude, S. E.

(1991):
First-person Plural: Multiple Personality and the Philosophy of Mind.
Routledge.

@

Braude, S. E.

(1996):
Multiple personality disorder and moral responsibility.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology ', vol. 3, pp. 37-54.

@

Braun, D.

(1991):
Content, causation, and cognitive science.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 69, pp. 375-89.

@

Braun, D.

(1995):
Causally relevant properties.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 9, pp. 447-75.

@

Breazeal, C.; Brooks, R.

(2004):
Robot emotions: A functional perspective.
In: J. Fellous (Ed.): 'Who Needs Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Brennan, A.

(1982):
Personal identity and personal survival.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 42, pp. 44-50.

@

Brennan, A.

(1984):
Survival.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 59, pp. 339-62.

@

Brennan, A.

(1987):
Discontinuity and identity.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 21, pp. 241-60.

@

Brennan, A.

(1988):
Conditions of Identity: A Study of Identity and Survival.
Oxford University Press.

@

Brennan, A. A.

(1987):
Survival and importance.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 47, pp. 225-30.

@

Brewer, B.

(1995):
Compulsion by reason (Mental Causation II).
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 69, pp. 237-53.

@

Bricke, J.

(1975):
Interaction and physiology.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 84, pp. 255-9.

@

Bricke, J.

(2000):
Desires, passions, and evaluations.
In: ' Southwest Philosophy Review ', vol. 16, pp. 59-65.

@

Bridges, J.

(2005):
Davidson's transcendental externalism.
In: ' 2005 '.

@

Bridges, J.

(2005):
Does informational semantics commit Euthypho's fallacy.
In: ' 2005 '.

@

Bringsjord, S.

(1991):
Is the connectionist-logicist debate one of AI's wonderful red herrings?.
In: ' Journal of Theoretical and Experimental Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 3, pp. 319-49.

@

Bringsjord, S.

(1992):
What Robots Can and Can't Be.
Kluwer.

@

Bringsjord, S.

(1994):
Could, how could we tell if, and should -- androids have inner lives?.
In: K. M. Ford; C. Glymour; P. Hayes (Ed.): 'Android Epistemology '.
MIT Press.

@

Bringsjord, S.

(1994):
Computation, among other things, is beneath us.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp. 469-88.

@

Bringsjord, S.

(1998):
Cognition is not computation: The argument from irreversibility.
In: ' 1998 '.

@

Bringsjord, S.

(2001):
Creativity, the Turing test, and the (better) Lovelace test.
In: ' Minds & Machines ', vol. 11, pp. 3-27.

@

Bringsjord, S.; Bello, P.; Ferrucci, D.

(2001):
Creativity, the Turing test, and the (better) Lovelace test.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 11, pp. 3-27.

@

Bringsjord, S.; Noel, R.

(2003):
Real robots and the missing thought-experiment in the Chinese room dialectic.
In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Bringsjord, S.; Zenzen, M.

(1997):
Cognition is not computation: The argument from irreversibility.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 113, pp. 285-320.

@

Broackes, J.

(1992):
The autonomy of colour.
In: D. Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): 'Reduction, Explanation, and Realism '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Broackes, J.

(1997):
The Nature of Colour.
Routledge.

@

Broad, C. D.

(1925):
The Mind and its Place in Nature.
Routledge and Kegan Paul.

@

Broad, C. D.

(1971):
Emotion and sentiment.
In: ' Critical Essays in Moral Theory '.

@

Broadbent, D.

(1985):
A question of levels: Comment on McClelland and Rumelhart.
In: ' Journal of Experimental Psychology: General ', vol. 114, pp. 189-92.

@

Brodbeck, M.

(1966):
Mental and physical: Identity versus sameness.
In: P. Feyerabend; G. Maxwell (Ed.): 'Mind, Matter, and Method: Essays in Philosophy and Science in Honor of Herbert Feigl '.
University of Minnesota Press.

@

Brook, A.; Stainton, R.

(1997):
Fodor's new theory of content and computation.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 12, pp. 459-74.

@

Brook, D.

(1992):
Substantial mind.
In: ' South African Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 1, pp. 15-21.

@

Brooks, D. H. M.

(1986):
Group minds.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 64, pp. 456-70.

@

Brooks, D. H. M.

(1994):
How to perform a reduction.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 54, pp. 803-14.

@

Brooks, R.

(1991):
Intelligence without representation.
In: ' Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 47, pp. 139-159.

@

Brown, C.

(1993):
Belief states and narrow content.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 8, pp. 343-67.

@

Brown, C.

(2002):
Narrow mental content.
In: ' 2002 '.

@

Brown, D. J.

(1993):
Swampman of La Mancha.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 23, pp. 327-48.

@

Brown, D. J.

(1996):
A furry tile about mental representation.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 185, pp. 448-66.

@

Brown, H.

(1986):
Sellars, concepts, and conceptual change.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 68, pp. 275-307.

@

Brown, J.

(1995):
The incompatibility of anti-individualism and privileged access.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 55, pp. 149-56.

@

Brown, J.

(1998):
Natural kind terms and recognitional capacities.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 107, pp. 275-303.

@

Brown, J.

(2000):
Critical reasoning, understanding and self-knowledge.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 61, pp. 659-676.

@

Brown, J.

(2000):
Reliabilism, knowledge, and mental content.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 100, pp. 115-35.

@

Brown, J.

(2001):
Anti-individualism and agnosticism.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 61, pp. 213-24.

@

Brown, J.

(2003):
The reductio argument and transmission of warrant.
In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge '.
MIT Press.

@

Brown, M. T.

(2001):
Multiple personality and personal identity.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 14, pp. 435-47.

@

Brown, R.; Herrstein, R.

(1981):
Icons and images.
In: N. Block (Ed.): 'Imagery '.
MIT Press.

@

Browne, D.

(1996):
Cognitive versatility.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 6, pp. 507-23.

@

Bruckner, A.

(2003):
Two transcendental arguments concerning self-knowledge.
In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge '.
MIT Press.

@

Bruecker, A.

(1998):
Shoemaker on second-order belief.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 58, pp. 361-64.

@

Brueckner A.

(2004):
Brewer on the McKinsey problem.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 64, pp. 41-43.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1990):
Scepticism about knowledge of content.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 99, pp. 447-51.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1992):
What an anti-individualist knows a priori.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 52, pp. 111-18.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1992):
Semantic answers to skepticism.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 73, pp. 200-19.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1993):
Skepticism and externalism.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 22, pp. 169-71.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1993):
Parfit on what matters in survival.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 70, pp. 1-22.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1994):
Knowledge of content and knowledge of the world.
In: ' Philosophical Review: ', vol. 103.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1995):
The characteristic thesis of anti-individualism.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 55, pp. 146-48.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1995):
Trying to get outside your own skin.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 23, pp. 79-111.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1997):
Externalism and memory.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 78, pp. 1-12.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1997):
Is scepticism about self-knowledge incoherent?.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 4, pp. 287-90.

@

Brueckner, A.

(1999):
Two recent approaches to self-knowledge.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 13, pp. 251-71.

@

Brueckner, A.

(2000):
Externalism and the a prioricity of self-knowledge.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 60, pp. 132-136.

@

Brueckner, A.

(2000):
Ambiguity and knowledge of content.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 60, pp. 257-60.

@

Brueckner, A.

(2001):
Defending Burge's thought experiment.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 55, pp. 387-391.

@

Brueckner, A.

(2001):
A priori knowledge of the world not easily available.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 104, pp. 109-114.

@

Brueckner, A.

(2001):
Problems for a recent account of introspective knowledge.
In: ' 2001 '.

@

Brueckner, A.

(2002):
Anti-individualism and analyticity.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 62, pp. 87-91.

@

Brueckner, A.

(2003):
Contents just aren't in the head.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 58, pp. 1-6.

@

Brueckner, A.

(2005):
Noordhof on McKinsey-Brown.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 65.

@

Bruner, J.

(1957):
On perceptual readiness.
In: ' Psychological Review ', vol. 65, pp. 14-21.

@

Bruns, M.; Soldati, G.

(1997):
Object-dependent and property-dependent concepts.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 48, pp. 185-208.

@

Bruntrup, G.

(1998):
Is psychophysical emergentism committed to dualism? The causal efficacy of emergent mental properties .
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 48, pp. 133-51.

@

Bub, J.

(1994):
Testing models of cognition through the analysis of brain-damaged patients.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 45, pp. 837-55.

@

Buchanan, B.

(1988):
AI as an experimental science.
In: J. Fetzer (Ed.): 'Aspects of AI '.
D.

@

Buck, R.

(1962):
Non-other minds.
In: R. Butler (Ed.): 'Analytic Philosophy '.
Barnes and Noble.

@

Buckley, J.; Hall, L.

(1999):
Self-knowledge and embodiment.
In: ' Southwest Philosophy Review ', vol. 15.

@

Buckley, R.

(2001):
Physicalism and the problem of mental causation.
In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research ', vol. 26, pp. 155-174.

@

Budd, M.

(1984):
Wittgenstein on meaning, interpretation and rules.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 58.

@

Buekens, F.

(1994):
Externalism, content, and causal histories.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 48, pp. 267-86.

@

Buford, T. O.

(1970):
Essays on Other Minds.
University of Illinois Press.

@

Buller, D. J.

(1992):
"Narrow"-minded breeds inaction.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 20, pp. 59-70.

@

Buller, D. J.

(1993):
Confirmation and the computational paradigm, or, why do you think they call it artificial intelligence? .
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 3, pp. 155-81.

@

Buller, D. J.

(1997):
Individualism and evolutionary psychology (or: In defense of "narrow" functions).
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 64, pp. 74-95.

@

Buller, D. J.

(1999):
DeFreuding evolutionary psychology: Adaptation and human motivation.
In: V. Hardcastle (Ed.): 'Where Biology Meets Philosophy '.
MIT Press.

@

Buller, D. J.

(2000):
A guided tour of evolutionary psychology.
In: ' 2000 '.

@

Buller, D. J.

(2005):
Adapting Minds: Evolutionary Psychology and the Persistent Quest for Human Nature.
MIT Press.

@

Buller, D. J.

(2005):
Evolutionary psychology: The emperor's new paradigm.
In: ' 2005 '.

@

Buller, D. J.; Hardcastle, V. G.

(2000):
Evolutionary psychology, meet developmental neurobiology: Against promiscuous modularity.
In: ' Brain and Mind ', vol. 1, pp. 307-25.

@

Bundy, A.

(1990):
What kind of field is AI?.
In: D. Partridge; Y. Wilks (Ed.): 'The Foundations of Artificial Intelligence: A Sourcebook '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Bunge, M.

(1977):
Emergence and the mind.
In: ' Neuroscience ', vol. 2, pp. 501-9.

@

Bunzl, M.

(1987):
Reductionism and the mental.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 24, pp. 181-9.

@

Burge, T.

(1979):
Individualism and the mental.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 4, pp. 73-122.

@

Burge, T.

(1982):
Other bodies.
In: A. Woodfield (Ed.): 'Thought and Object '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Burge, T.

(1982):
Two thought experiments reviewed.
In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic ', vol. 23, pp. 284-94.

@

Burge, T.

(1986):
Intellectual norms and foundations of mind.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 83, pp. 697-720.

@

Burge, T.

(1986):
Individualism and psychology.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 95, pp. 3-45.

@

Burge, T.

(1986):
Individualism and psychology.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 95, pp. 3-45.

@

Burge, T.

(1986):
Intellectual norms and foundations of mind.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 83, pp. 697-720.

@

Burge, T.

(1988):
Individualism and self-knowledge.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 85, pp. 649-63.

@

Burge, T.

(1989):
Individuation and causation in psychology.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 707, pp. 303-22.

@

Burge, T.

(1992):
Philosophy of language and mind: 1950-1990.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 100, pp. 3-52.

@

Burge, T.

(1993):
Concepts, definitions, and meaning.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 24, pp. 309-25.

@

Burge, T.

(1993):
Mind-body causation and explanatory practice.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Burge, T.

(1995):
Intentional properties and causation.
In: C. Macdonald; G. Macdonald (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Psychology: Debates about Psychological Explanation '.
Blackwell.

@

Burge, T.

(1996):
Our entitlement to self-knowledge.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 96, pp. 91-116.

@

Burge, T.

(1998):
Memory and self-knowledge.
In: P. Ludlow; N. Martin (Ed.): 'Externalism and Self-Knowledge '.
CSLI.

@

Burge, T.

(1999):
A century of deflation and a moment about self-knowledge.
In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association ', vol. 73, pp. 25-46.

@

Burge, T.

(2000):
Reason and the first person.
In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Burge, T.

(2003):
Davidson and forms of anti-individualism: Reply to Hahn.
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Burge, T.

(2003):
Descartes, bare concepts, and anti-individualism: Reply to Normore. In (M. Hahn & B. Ramberg, eds) Reflections and Replies. MIT Press. Burge, T. 2003. The thought experiments: Reply to Do
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Burge, T.

(2003):
The indexical strategy: Reply to Owens. In (M. Hahn & B. Ramberg, eds) Reflections and Replies. MIT Press. Burge, T. 2003. Psychology and the environment: Reply to Chomsky .
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Burge, T.

(2003):
Replies from Tyler Burge. In (M. Frapolli & E. Romero, eds) Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind. CSLI. Donnellan, K. 2003. Burge's thought experiments .
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Burge, T.

(2003):
Mental agency in authoritative self-knowledge: Reply to Kobes.
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Burge, T.

(2003):
Some reflections on scepticism: Reply to Stroud.
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Burge, T.

(2003):
Epiphenomenalism: Reply to Dretske.
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Burge, T.

(2003):
Concepts, conceptions, reflective understanding: Reply to Peacocke.
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Burge, T.

(2004):
Memory and persons.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 112.

@

Burgos, J.

(2004):
Realism about behavior.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 32, pp. 69-95.

@

Burks, A. W.

(1973):
Logic, computers, and men.
In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association ', vol. 46, pp. 39-57.

@

Bush, E.

(1974):
Rorty revisited.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 25, pp. 33-42.

@

Bushnell, D. E.

(1993):
Identity, psychological continuity, and rationality.
In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research ', vol. 18, pp. 15-24.

@

Buss, D. M.

(1999):
Evolutionary Psychology: The New Science of the Mind.
Allyn and Bacon.

@

Butler, K.

(1991):
Towards a connectionist cognitive architecture.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 6, pp. 252-72.

@

Butler, K.

(1992):
The physiology of desire.
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 13, pp. 69-88.

@

Butler, K.

(1993):
Connectionism, classical cognitivism, and the relation between cognitive and implementational levels of analysis .
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 6, pp. 321-33.

@

Butler, K.

(1993):
On Clark on systematicity and connectionism.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 44, pp. 37-44.

@

Butler, K.

(1994):
Neural constraints in cognitive science.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp. 129-62.

@

Butler, K.

(1995):
Content, context, and compositionality.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 10, pp. 3-24.

@

Butler, K.

(1995):
Compositionality in cognitive models: The real issue.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 78, pp. 153-62.

@

Butler, K.

(1995):
Representation and computation in a deflationary assessment of connectionist cognitive science.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 104, pp. 71-97.

@

Butler, K.

(1996):
Content, causal powers, and context.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 63, pp. 105-14.

@

Butler, K.

(1996):
Individualism and Marr's computational theory of vision.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp. 313-37.

@

Butler, K.

(1996):
Content, computation, and individualism in vision theory.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 56, pp. 146-54.

@

Butler, K.

(1997):
Externalism, internalism, and knowledge of content.
In: ' philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 57, pp. 773-800.

@

Butler, K.

(1998):
Internal Affairs: Making Room for Psychosemantic Internalism.
Kluwer.

@

Butler, K.

(1998):
Content, computation, and individuation.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 114, pp. 277-92.

@

Butler, K.

(1998):
Externalism and skepticism.
In: ' Dialogue ', vol. 37, pp. 13-34.

@

Butler, K.

(2000):
Problems for semantic externalism and a priori refutations of skeptical arguments.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 54, pp. 29-49.

@

Buttazzo, G.

(2001):
Artificial consciousness: Utopia or real possibility?.
In: ' Computer ', vol. 34, pp. 24-30.

@

Button, G.; Coulter, J.; Lee, J. R. E.; Sharrock, W.

(1995):
Computers, Minds, and Conduct.
Polity Press.

@

Bynum, T. W.

(1985):
Artificial intelligence, biology, and intentional states.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 16, pp. 355-77.

@

Byrne, A.

(1996):
On misinterpreting Kripke's Wittgenstein.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 56.

@

Byrne, A.

(1998):
Interpretivism.
In: ' European Review of Philosophy ', vol. 3.

@

Byrne, A.

(2001):
Do colors look like dispositions? Reply to Langsam and others.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 51.

@

Byrne, A.

(2002):
Yes, Virginia, lemons are yellow.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 108, pp. 213-22.

@

Byrne, A.

(2003):
Color and similarity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66:641-665. Campbell, J. 1993. A simple view of colour .
In: J. Haldane; C. Wright (Ed.): 'Reality, Representation, and Projection '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Byrne, A.; Hilbert, D. R.

(1997):
Readings on Color, Volume 1: The Philosophy of Color.
MIT Press.

@

Byrne, A.; Hilbert, D. R.

(1997):
Readings on Color, Volume 2: The Science of Color.
MIT Press.

@

Byrne, A.; Hilbert, D. R.

(1997):
Colors and reflectances.
In: A. Byrne; D. R. Hilbert (Ed.): 'Readings on Color, Volume 1: The Philosophy of Color '.
MIT Press.

@

Byrne, A.; Hilbert, D. R.

(2004):
Hardin, Tye, and color physicalism.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 101, pp. 37-43.

@

Byrne, A.; Pryor, J.

(2006):
Bad intensions.
In: M. Garcia-Carpintero; J. Macia (Ed.): 'Two-Dimensional Semantics: Foundations and Applications '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Cain, M. J.

(1999):
Fodor's attempt to naturalize mental content.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 49, pp. 520-26.

@

Cain, M. J.

(2000):
Individualism, twin scenarios and visual content.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 13, pp. 441-463.

@

Cain, M. J.

(2002):
Fodor: Language, Mind, and Philosophy.
Polity Press.

@

Calhoun, C.

(2004):
Subjectivity and emotion.
In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Callaway, H. G.

(1992):
Meaning holism and semantic realism.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 46, pp. 41-59.

@

Callaway, H. G.

(1995):
Intentionality naturalized: Continuity, reconstruction, and instrumentalism.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 49, pp. 147-68.

@

Calvin, W.

(2004):
A Brief History of the Mind: From Apes to Intellect and Beyond.
Oxford University Press.

@

Cam, P.

(1978):
"Rorty revisited", or "Rorty revised".
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 33, pp. 377-86.

@

Cam, P.

(1984):
Dennett on intelligent storage.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 45, pp. 247-62.

@

Cam, P.

(1987):
Propositions about images.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 48, pp. 335-8.

@

Cam, P.

(1988):
Modularity, rationality, and higher cognition.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 53, pp. 279-94.

@

Cam, P.

(1990):
Searle on strong AI.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 68, pp. 103-8.

@

Cam, P.

(1990):
Insularity and the persistence of perceptual illusion.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 50, pp. 231-5.

@

Campbell, C. A.

(1951):
Is "free will" a pseudoproblem?.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 60, pp. 441-65.

@

Campbell, C. A.

(1953):
Ryle on the intellect.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 3, pp. 115-38.

@

Campbell, C. A.

(1967):
In Defense of Free Will.
Allen and Unwin.

@

Campbell, D.

(2005):
Joint attention and common knowledge. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler, eds) Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds .
In: ' 2005 '.

@

Campbell, J.

(1997):
The realism of memory.
In: R. Heck (Ed.): 'Language, Thought, and Logic: Essays in Honour of Michael Dummett '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Campbell, J.

(1997):
The structure of time in autobiographical memory.
In: ' European Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 5, pp. 105-17.

@

Campbell, J.

(1999):
Immunity to error through misidentification and the meaning of a referring term.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 26, pp. 89-104.

@

Campbell, J.

(1999):
Schizophrenia, the space of reasons and thinking as a motor process.
In: ' Monist ', vol. 82.

@

Campbell, J.

(2001):
Rationality, meaning, and the analysis of delusion.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, ', vol. 8, pp. 89-100.

@

Campbell, J.

(2002):
Joint attention and simulation.
In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action '.
John Benjamins.

@

Campbell, J.

(2002):
Berkeley's puzzle.
In: T. Gendler; J. Hawthorne (Ed.): 'Conceivability and Possibility '.
MIT Press.

@

Campbell, J. K.

(1997):
A compatibilist theory of alternate possibilities.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 67, pp. 339-44.

@

Campbell, K.

(1969):
Colours.
In: R. Brown; C. Rollins (Ed.): 'Contemporary Philosophy in Australia '.
Humanities Press.

@

Campbell, K.

(1982):
The implications of Land's theory of colour vision.
In: L. Cohen (Ed.): 'Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science '.
, Vol.

@

Campbell, K.

(1983):
Abstract particulars and the philosophy of mind.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 61, pp. 129-41.

@

Campbell, K.

(1993):
David Armstrong and realism about colour.
In: J. Bacon; K. Campbell; L. Reinhardt (Ed.): 'Ontology, Causality, and Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Campbell, N.

(1997):
The standard objection to anomalous monism.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 75, pp. 373-82.

@

Campbell, N.

(1998):
Anomalous monism and the charge of epiphenomenalism.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 52, pp. 23-39.

@

Campbell, N.

(2002):
Physicalism, supervenience, and dependence: a reply to Botterell.
In: ' Dialogue ', vol. 41, pp. 163-167.

@

Campbell, S.

(2000):
Strawson, Parfit and impersonality.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 30, pp. 207-225.

@

Campbell, S.

(2001):
Is connectedess necessary to what mattres in survival?.
In: ' Ration ', vol. 14, pp. 193-202.

@

Campbell, S.

(2001):
Persons and substances.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 104, pp. 253-67.

@

Campbell, S.

(2004):
Rapid psychological change.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 64, pp. 256-264.

@

Campbell, S.

(2004):
Can you survive a brain-zap?.
In: ' Theoria ', vol. 70.

@

Canali, S.

(2004):
On the concept of the psychological.
In: ' Topoi ', vol. 23, pp. 177-86.

@

Candlish, S.

(1970):
Mind, brain, and identity.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 79, pp. 502-18.

@

Candlish, S.

(1975):
Mental images and pictorial properties.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 84, pp. 260-2.

@

Canfield, J.

(1996):
The community view.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 105, pp. 469-488.

@

Caplain, G.

(1995):
Is consciousness a computational property?.
In: ' Informatica ', vol. 19, pp. 615-19.

@

Carleton, L.

(1984):
Programs, language understanding, and Searle.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 59, pp. 219-30.

@

Carlson, E.

(2002):
In defense of the Mind argument.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 29, pp. 393-400.

@

Carnap, R.

(1959):
Psychology in physical language.
In: Ayer (Ed.): 'Logical Positivism '.
Free Press.

@

Carney, J.

(1971):
The compatibility of mind-body identity with dualism.
In: ' 1971 '.

@

Carrier, L.

(1973):
Professor Shaffer's refutation of behaviourism.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 80, pp. 249-52.

@

Carruthers, P.

(1984):
Baker and Hacker's Wittgenstein.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 58, pp. 451-79.

@

Carruthers, P.

(1985):
Ruling-out realism.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 15, pp. 61-78.

@

Carruthers, P.

(1986):
Introducing Persons: Theories and Arguments in the Philosophy of Mind.
SUNY Press.

@

Carruthers, P.

(1996):
Simulation and self-knowledge: A defence of the theory-theory.
In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Carruthers, P.

(2000):
Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Carruthers, P.

(2003):
On Fodor's problem.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 18, pp. 502-523.

@

Carruthers, P.

(2003):
Moderately massive modularity.
In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Mind and Persons '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Carruthers, P.

(2003):
The Nature of Mind.
Routledge.

@

Carruthers, P.

(2004):
Practical reasoning in a modular mind.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 19, pp. 259-278.

@

Carruthers, P.; Smith, P.

(1996):
Theories of Theories of Mind.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Carter, W.

(1999):
Will I be a dead person?.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 59.

@

Carter, W. R.

(1974):
On incorrigibility and eliminative materialism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 28, pp. 113-21.

@

Cartwright, H. M.

(1987):
Ruminations on an account of personal identity.
In: J. J. Thomson (Ed.): 'On Being and Saying: Essays on Honor of Richard Cartwright '.
MIT Press.

@

Cartwright, H. M.

(1993):
On two arguments for the indeterminacy of personal identity.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 95, pp. 241-273.

@

Cascardi, A. J.

(1984):
Remembering.
In: ' Review of Metaphysics ', vol. 38, pp. 275-302.

@

Case, J.

(2004):
Offloading memory to the environment: A quantitative example.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 14, pp. 387-89.

@

Casey, E. S.

(1987):
Remembering: A Phenomenological Study.
Indiana University Press.

@

Casey, E. S.

(2003):
Imagination, fantasy, hallucination, and memory.
In: J. Philips; J. Morley (Ed.): 'Imagination and its Pathologies '.
MIT Press.

@

Cassam, Q.

(1993):
Parfit on persons.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 93, pp. 17-37.

@

Cassam, Q.

(1994):
Self-Knowledge.
Oxford University Press.

@

Cassam, Q.

(1995):
Introspection and bodily self-ascription.
In: J. Bermudez; A. Marcel; N. Eilan (Ed.): 'The Body and the Self '.
MIT Press.

@

Cassam, Q.

(1998):
Self-knowledge, a priori knowledge, and the cognitive structure of the mind.
In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Cassam, Q.

(2002):
Representing bodies.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 15, pp. 315-334.

@

Castaneda, H.

(1962):
Criteria, analogy, and knowledge of other minds.
In: ' 1962 '.

@

Caston, V.

(1997):
Epiphenomenalisms, ancient and modern.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 106, pp. 309-363.

@

Catalano, J.

(2000):
Thinking Matter: Consciousness from Aristotle to Putnam and Sartre.
Routledge.

@

Causey, R. L.

(1972):
Attribute identities in microreductions.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 69, pp. 407-22.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1990):
Syntactic transformations on distributed representations.
In: ' Connection Science ', vol. 2, pp. 53-62.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1992):
Subsymbolic computation and the Chinese Room.
In: J. Dinsmore (Ed.): 'The Symbolic and Connectionist Paradigms: Closing the Gap '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1992):
Subsymbolic computation and the Chinese Room.
In: J. Dinsmore (Ed.): 'The Symbolic and Connectionist Paradigms: Closing the Gap '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1993):
Connectionism and compositionality: Why Fodor and Pylyshyn were wrong.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 6, pp. 305-319.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1994):
A computational foundation for the study of cognition.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1994):
On implementing a computation.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp. 391-402.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1996):
The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory.
Oxford University Press.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1996):
Supervenience and materialism.
In: ' The Conscious Mind '.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1996):
Minds, machines, and mathematics.
In: ' Psyche ', vol. 2, pp. 11-20.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1996):
Does a rock implement every finite-state automaton?.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 108, pp. 309-33.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2002):
The components of content.
In: D. Chalmers (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2002):
The components of content.
In: D. Chalmers (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2002):
On sense and intension.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 16, pp. 135-82.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2003):
Consciousness and its place in nature.
In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Mind '.
Blackwell.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2003):
The nature of narrow content.
In: ' Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp. 46-66.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2003):
The nature of narrow content.
In: ' Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp. 46-66.

@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2004):
Epistemic two-dimensional semantics.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 118, pp. 153-226.

@

Chalmers, D. J.; French, R. M.; Hofstadter, D. R.

(1992):
High-level perception, representation, and analogy: A critique of AI methodology.
In: ' 1992 '.

@

Chambers, D.; Reisberg, D.

(1985):
Can mental images be ambiguous?.
In: ' ' Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance ', vol. 11, pp. 317-28.

@

Chambers, D.; Reisberg, D.

(1992):
What an image depicts depends on what an image means.
In: ' Cognitive Psychology ', vol. 24, pp. 145-74.

@

Champlin, T. S.

(1992):
Solitary rule-following.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 67, pp. 285-306.

@

Chan, D. K.

(2004):
Are there extrinsic desires?.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 38, pp. 326-50.

@

Chandrasekaran, B.; Goel, A.; Allemang, D.

(1988):
Connectionism and information-processing abstractions.
In: ' AI Magazine ', vol. 24.

@

Changeux, J.; Ricoeur, P.

(2002):
What Makes Us Think? A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain .
Princeton.

@

Chapman, C. R.; Nakakura, Y.; Chapman, C. N.

(2000):
Pain and folk theory.
In: ' Brain and Mind ', vol. 1, pp. 209-222.

@

Chappell, T.

(1995):
Personal identity, R-relatedness, and the empty question argument.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 45, pp. 88-92.

@

Chappell, T.

(1998):
Reductionism about persons; and what matters.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 98, pp. 41-58.

@

Chappell, V. C.

(1963):
The concept of dreaming.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 13, pp. 193-213.

@

Chari, C.

(1963):
Further comments on minds, machines and Godel.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 38, pp. 175-8.

@

Charland, L. C.

(1995):
Feeling and representing: Computational theory and the modularity of affect.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 105, pp. 273-301.

@

Charland, L. C.

(1997):
Reconciling cognitive and perceptual theories of emotion: A representational proposal.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 64, pp. 555-579.

@

Charland, L. C.

(2002):
The natural kind status of emotion.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 53, pp. 511-37.

@

Charles, D.

(1992):
Supervenience, composition, and physicalism.
In: D. Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): 'Reduction, Explanation and Realism '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Chase, J.

(2001):
Is externalism about content inconsistent with internalism about justification?.
In: ' Australasian Jouenal of Philosophy ', vol. 79, pp. 227-46.

@

Chater, N. and Oaksford, M.

(2002):
The rational analysis of human cognition.
In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature '.
Clarendon.

@

Chater, N.; Oaksford, M.

(1990):
Autonomy, implementation and cognitive architecture: A reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 34, pp. 93-107.

@

Chater, N.; Oaksford, M.

(1996):
The falsity of folk theories: Implications for psychology and philosophy.
In: W. O'Donahue; R. Kitchener (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of Psychology '.
Sage Publications.

@

Chater, N.; Vitanyi, P.

(2003):
Simplicity: A unifying principle in cognitive science?.
In: ' Trends in Cognitive Science ', vol. 7, pp. 19-22.

@

Chemero, A.

(2002):
Reconsidering Ryle: Editor's introduction.
In: ' Electronic Journal of Anlaytic Philosophy ', vol. 7.

@

Cheney, D. L.; Seyfarth, R. M.

(1990):
How Monkeys See the World: Inside the Mind of Another Species.
University of Chicago Press.

@

Cheng, K.

(1997):
Davidson's action theory and epiphenomenalism.
In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research ', vol. 22, pp. 81-95.

@

Cherniak, C.

(1981):
Minimal rationality.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 90, pp. 161-83.

@

Cherniak, C.

(1983):
Rationality and the structure of memory.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 57, pp. 163-86.

@

Cherniak, C.

(1983):
Rationality and the structure of human memory.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 57, pp. 163-86.

@

Cherniak, C.

(1986):
Minimal Rationality.
MIT Press.

@

Cherniak, C.

(1991):
Meta-neuroanatomy: The myth of the unbounded mind/brain. In (E.
In: ' 1991 '.

@

Cherniak, C.

(1994):
Philosophy and computational neuroanatomy.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 73, pp. 89-107.

@

Chien, A. J.

(1996):
Why the mind may not be modular.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 6, pp. 1-32.

@

Chihara, C.

(1965):
What dreams are made of.
In: ' Theoria ', vol. 31, pp. 145-58.

@

Chihara, C.

(1972):
On alleged refutations of mechanism using Godel's incompleteness results.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 64, pp. 507-26.

@

Chihara, C.; Fodor, J.

(1965):
Operationalism and ordinary language: A critique of Wittgenstein.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 2, pp. 281-95.

@

Child, W.

(1993):
Anomalism, uncodifiability, and psychophysical relations.
In: ' 1993 '.

@

Child, W.

(2002):
Reply to 'Simulation theory and mental concepts'.
In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action '.
John Benjamins.

@

Chisholm, R.

(1952):
Intentionality and the theory of signs.
In: ' 1952 '.

@

Chisholm, R.

(1955):
A note on Carnap's meaning analysis.
In: ' 1955 '.

@

Chisholm, R.

(1958):
Sentences about believing.
In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 2.

@

Chisholm, R. M.

(1976):
Person and Object: A Metaphysical Study.
Open Court.

@

Chomsky, N.

(1967):
Recent contributions to the theory of innate ideas.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 17, pp. 2-11.

@

Chomsky, N.

(1969):
Linguistics and philosophy.
In: S. Hook (Ed.): 'Language and Philosophy '.
New York University Press.

@

Chomsky, N.

(1975):
On cognitive capacity.
In: ' Reflections on Language '.

@

Chomsky, N.

(1980):
Rules and representations.
In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences ', vol. 3, pp. 1-61.

@

Chomsky, N.

(1980):
Discussion of Putnam's comments.
In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.): 'Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky '.
Harvard University Press.

@

Chomsky, N.

(2003):
Internalist explorations.
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Chomsky, N.; Fodor, J. A.

(1980):
The inductivist fallacy.
In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.): 'Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky '.
Harvard University Press.

@

Chrisley, R. L.

(1994):
Taking embodiment seriously: Nonconceptual content and robotics.
In: K. M. Ford; C. Glymour; P. Hayes (Ed.): 'Android Epistemology '.
MIT Press.

@

Chrisley, R. L.

(1994):
Why everything doesn't realize every computation.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp. 403-20.

@

Chrisley, R. L.

(1994):
Taking embodiment seriously: Nonconceptual content and robotics.
In: K. M. Ford; C. Glymour; P. Hayes (Ed.): 'Android Epistemology '.
MIT Press.

@

Christensen, D.

(1992):
Causal powers and conceptual connections.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 52, pp. 163-8.

@

Christensen, W. D.; Hooker C. A.

(2004):
Representation and the meaning of life.
In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Representation in Mind '.
Elsevier.

@

Christiansen, M. H.; Chater, N.

(1994):
Generalization and connectionist language learning.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 9, pp. 273-87.

@

Chung, M.; Fulford, K.; Graham, G.

(2005):
The Philosophical Understanding of Schizophrenia.
Oxford University Press.

@

Church, J.

(2003):
Depression, depth, and the imagination.
In: J. Philips; J. Morley (Ed.): 'Imagination and its Pathologies '.
MIT Press.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1979):
Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1981):
Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 78, pp. 67-90.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1982):
Is `thinker' a natural kind?.
In: ' Dialogue ', vol. 21, pp. 223-38.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1984):
Matter and Consciousness.
MIT Press.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1985):
On the speculative nature of our self-conception.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplement ', vol. 11, pp. 157-173.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1986):
Some reductive strategies in cognitive neurobiology.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 95, pp. 279-309.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1988):
Folk psychology and the explanation of human behavior.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 62, pp. 209-21.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1988):
Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality: A reply to Jerry Fodor.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 55, pp. 167-87.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1989):
A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science.
MIT Press.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1989):
On the nature of theories: A neurocomputational perspective.
In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 14.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1989):
On the nature of explanation: A PDP approach.
In: ' A Neurocomputational Perspective '.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1993):
Theory, taxonomy, and methodology: A reply to Haldane's "Understanding folk".
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 67, pp. 313-19.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1993):
Evaluating our self-conception.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 8, pp. 211-22.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1995):
The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain.
MIT Press.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1998):
Conceptual similarity across sensory and neural diversity: The Fodor/Lepore challenge answered.
In: ' Journal Of Philosophy ', vol. 95, pp. 5-32.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(1998):
Conceptual similarity across sensory and neural diversity: The Fodor/Lepore challenge answered.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 95, pp. 5-32.

@

Churchland, P. M.

(2005):
Functionalism at forty: A critical retrospective.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 102, pp. 33-50.

@

Churchland, P. M.; Churchland, P. S.

(1983):
Stalking the wild epistemic engine.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 17, pp. 5-20.

@

Churchland, P. M.; Churchland, P. S.

(1983):
Stalking the wild epistemic engine.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 17, pp. 5-18.

@

Churchland, P. M.; Churchland, P. S.

(1990):
Could a machine think?.
In: ' Scientific American ', vol. 262, no. 1, pp. 32-37.

@

Churchland, P. M.; Churchland, P. S.

(1997):
Recent work on consciousness: Philosophical, theoretical, and empirical.
In: ' Seminars in Neurology ', vol. 17, pp. 179-86.

@

Churchland, P. S.

(1978):
Fodor on language learning.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 38, pp. 149-59.

@

Churchland, P. S.

(1980):
Language, thought, and information processing.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 14, pp. 147-70.

@

Churchland, P. S.

(1980):
A perspective on mind-brain research.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 77, pp. 185-207.

@

Churchland, P. S.

(1981):
Is determinism self-refuting?.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 90, pp. 99-101.

@

Churchland, P. S.

(1982):
Mind-brain reduction: New light from philosophy of science.
In: ' Neuroscience ', vol. 7, pp. 1041-7.

@

Churchland, P. S.

(1986):
Neurophilosophy: Toward A Unified Science of the Mind-Brain.
MIT Press.

@

Churchland, P. S.

(1987):
Epistemology in the age of neuroscience.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 84, pp. 546-53.

@

Churchland, P. S.

(2002):
Brain-Wise: Studies in Neurophilosophy.
MIT Press.

@

Churchland, P. S.; Sejnowski, T.

(1989):
Neural representation and neural computation.
In: L. Nadel (Ed.): 'Neural Connections, Mental Computations '.
MIT Press.

@

Churchland, P. S.; Sejnowski, T.

(1989):
Neural representation and neural computation.
In: L. Nadel (Ed.): 'Neural Connections, Mental Computations '.
MIT Press.

@

Clapin, H.

(1991):
Connectionism isn't magic.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp. 167-84.

@

Clapin, H.

(1997):
Problems with principle P.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 78, pp. 261-77.

@

Clapin, H.

(2002):
Philosophy and Mental Representation.
Oxford University Press.

@

Clapin, H.

(2002):
Tacit representation in functional architecture.
In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Mental Representation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Clapin, H.

(2004):
Representation in Mind: New Approaches to Mental Representation.
Elsevier.

@

Clapp, L.

(2001):
Disjunctive properties: multiple realizations.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 98, pp. 111-136.

@

Clark, A.

(1980):
Psychological Models and Neural Mechanisms: An Examination of Reductionism in Psychology.
Oxford University Press.

@

Clark, A.

(1986):
Psychofunctionalism and chauvinism.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 53, pp. 535-59.

@

Clark, A.

(1986):
A biological metaphor.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 1, pp. 45-64.

@

Clark, A.

(1987):
The kludge in the machine.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 2, pp. 277-300.

@

Clark, A.

(1987):
From folk psychology to naive psychology.
In: ' Cognitive Science ', vol. 11, pp. 139-54.

@

Clark, A.

(1987):
Being there: Why implementation matters to cognitive science.
In: ' AI Review ', vol. 1, pp. 231-44.

@

Clark, A.

(1988):
Thoughts, sentences and cognitive science.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 1, pp. 263-78.

@

Clark, A.

(1989):
Connectionism, nonconceptual content, and representational redescription.

@

Clark, A.

(1989):
Beyond eliminativism.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 4, pp. 251-79.

@

Clark, A.

(1989):
Microcognition.
MIT Press.

@

Clark, A.

(1990):
Belief, opinion and consciousness.
In: ' 1990 '.

@

Clark, A.

(1990):
Connectionist minds.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 90, pp. 83-102.

@

Clark, A.

(1990):
Connectionism, competence and explanation.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 41, pp. 195-222.

@

Clark, A.

(1991):
Radical ascent.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 65, pp. 211-27.

@

Clark, A.

(1991):
In defense of explicit rules.
In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Clark, A.

(1993):
Mice, shrews, and misrepresentation.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 90, pp. 290-310.

@

Clark, A.

(1993):
Associative Engines: Connectionism, Concepts, and Representational Change.
MIT Press.

@

Clark, A.

(1993):
Superpositional connectionism: A reply to Marinov.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 3, pp. 271-81.

@

Clark, A.

(1994):
Beliefs and desires incorporated.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 91, pp. 404-25.

@

Clark, A.

(1994):
Representational trajectories in connectionist learning.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp. 317-32.

@

Clark, A.

(1995):
Moving minds: Situating content in the service of real-time success.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 9, pp. 89-104.

@

Clark, A.

(1995):
Moving minds: Situating content in the service of real-time success.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 9, pp. 89-104.

@

Clark, A.

(1996):
Dealing in futures: Folk psychology and the role of representations in cognitive science.
In: R. McCauley (Ed.): 'The Churchlands and their Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Clark, A.

(1996):
True theories, false colors.
In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement ', vol. 63, pp. 143-50.

@

Clark, A.

(1997):
Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again.
MIT Press.

@

Clark, A.

(1997):
Embodiment and the philosophy of mind.
In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Clark, A.

(1998):
Time and mind.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 95, pp. 354-76.

@

Clark, A.

(2001):
Reasons, robots and the extended mind.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 16.

@

Clark, A.

(2001):
Reasons, robots and the extended mind.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 16.

@

Clark, A.

(2002):
The roots of 'norm-hungriness'. In (H. Clapin, ed) Philosophy and Mental Representation. Oxford University Press. Clark, A. 2002. Minds, brains, and tools .
In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Mental Representation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Clark, A.

(2002):
Artificial intelligence.
In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind '.
Blackwell.

@

Clark, A.

(2003):
Natural-Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies and the Future of Human Intelligence.
Oxford University Press.

@

Clark, A.

(2003):
Natural-Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence. Oxford University Press. Clark, A. 2004. Embodiment and the philosophy of mind .
In: A. Peruzzi (Ed.): 'Mind and Causality '.
John Benjamins.

@

Clark, A.

(2005):
Intrinsic content, active memory, and the extended mind.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 65, pp. 1-11.

@

Clark, A. and Toribio, J.

(1994):
Doing without representing.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 101, pp. 401-31.

@

Clark, A.; Chalmers, D. J.

(1998):
The extended mind.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 58, pp. 7-19.

@

Clark, A.; Chalmers, D. J.

(1998):
The extended mind.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 58, pp. 7-19.

@

Clark, A.; Karmiloff-Smith, A.

(1994):
The cognizer's innards: A psychological and philosophical perspective on the development of thought .
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 8, pp. 487-519.

@

Clark, A.; Thornton, S.

(1997):
Trading spaces: Computation, representation, and the limits of uninformed learning.
In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences ', vol. 20, pp. 57-66.

@

Clark, S. R. L.

(1987):
The description and evaluation of animal emotion.
In: C. Blakemore; S. Greenfield (Ed.): 'Mindwaves '.
Blackwell.

@

Clark, S. R. L.

(1991):
How many selves make me?.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 29, pp. 213-33.

@

Clark, S. R. L.

(1996):
Minds, memes, and multiples.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology ', vol. 3, pp. 21-28.

@

Clark, T.

(1992):
The Turing test as a novel form of hermeneutics.
In: ' International Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 24, pp. 17-31.

@

Clarke, J.

(1971):
Mental structure and the identity theory.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 80, pp. 521-30.

@

Clarke, J.

(1972):
Turing machines and the mind-body problem.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 23, pp. 1-12.

@

Clarke, M.

(1996):
Darwinian algorithms and indexical representation.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 63, pp. 27-48.

@

Clarke, R.

(1992):
Free will and the conditions of moral responsibility.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 66, pp. 53-72.

@

Clarke, R.

(1993):
Toward a credible agent-causal account of free will.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 27, pp. 191-203.

@

Clarke, R.

(1996):
Agent causation and event causation in the production of free action.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 24, pp. 19-48.

@

Clarke, R.

(1997):
On the possibility of rational free action.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 88, pp. 37-57.

@

Clarke, R.

(1999):
Nonreductive physicalism and the causal powers of the mental.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 51, pp. 295-322.

@

Clarke, R.

(2000):
Modest libertarianism.
In: ' Philosopical Perspectives ', vol. 14, pp. 21-46.

@

Clarke, R.

(2002):
Libertarian views: Critical survey of noncausal and event-causal accounts of free agency.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Clarke, R.

(2002):
Free will.
In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind '.
Blackwell.

@

Clarke, R.

(2002):
Libertarian views: Noncausal and event-causal sccounts of free agency.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Clayton, P.

(2004):
Mind and Emergence: From Quantum to Consciousness.
Oxford University Press.

@

Cleeremans, A.; French, R. M.

(1996):
From chicken squawking to cognition: Levels of description and the computational approach in psychology .
In: ' Psychologica Belgica ', vol. 36, pp. 5-29.

@

Cleland, C.

(1993):
Is the Church-Turing thesis true?.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 3, pp. 283-312.

@

Cleland, C. E.

(1995):
Effective procedures and computable functions.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 5, pp. 9-23.

@

Cleve, van, J.

(1990):
Supervenience and closure.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 58, pp. 225-38.

@

Cleve, van, J.

(1990):
Mind -- dust or magic? Panpsychism versus emergence.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 4, pp. 215-226.

@

Cliff, D.

(1990):
Computational neuroethology: A provisional manifesto.

@

Cling, A.

(1989):
Eliminative materialism and self-referential inconsistency.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 56, pp. 53-75.

@

Cling, A.

(1990):
Disappearance and knowledge.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 57, pp. 226-47.

@

Cling, A.

(1991):
The empirical virtues of belief.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 4, pp. 303-23.

@

Coates, P.

(1995):
Kripke's skeptical paradox: Normativeness and meaning.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 1986, pp. 77-80.

@

Coates, P.

(1997):
Meaning, mistake, and miscalculation.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 7, pp. 171-97.

@

Coburn, R.

(1963):
Shaffer on the identity of mental states and brain processes.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 60, pp. 89-92.

@

Coburn, R. C.

(1963):
Shaffer on the identity of mental states and brain processes.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 60.

@

Cockburn, D.

(1991):
Human Beings.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Cockburn, D.

(1994):
Human beings and giant squids (on ascribing human sensations and emotions to non-human creatures).
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 69, pp. 135-50.

@

Coder, D.

(1969):
Godel's theorem and mechanism.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 44, pp. 234-7.

@

Coder, D.

(1973):
The fundamental error of central-state materialism.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 10, pp. 289-98.

@

Cohen, B.

(1995):
Patterns lost: Indeterminism and Dennett's realism about beliefs.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 76, pp. 17-31.

@

Cohen, J.

(2003):
Color: A functionalist approach. Philosophical Studies 113:1-42. Cohen, J. 2003. On the structural properties of the colors .
In: ' Australian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 81, pp. 78-95.

@

Cohen, L. J.

(1955):
Can there be artificial minds?.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 16, pp. 36-41.

@

Cohen, L. J.

(1979):
On the psychology of prediction: Whose is the fallacy?.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 7, pp. 385-407.

@

Cohen, L. J.

(1980):
Whose is the fallacy? A rejoinder to Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 8, pp. 89-92.

@

Cohen, L. J.

(1981):
Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated?.
In: ' 1981 '.

@

Cohen, L. J.

(1986):
What sorts of machines can understand the symbols they use?.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 60, pp. 81-96.

@

Cohen, L. J.

(1986):
The Dialogue of Reason.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Cohen, L. J.

(1996):
Does belief exist?.
In: A. Clark; P. Millican (Ed.): 'Connectionism, Concepts, and Folk Psychology '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Cole, D. J.

(1984):
Thought and thought experiments.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 45, pp. 431-44.

@

Cole, D. J.

(1991):
Artificial intelligence and personal identity.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 88, pp. 399-417.

@

Cole, D. J.

(1991):
Artificial minds: Cam on Searle.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 69, pp. 329-33.

@

Cole, D. J.

(1994):
The causal powers of CPUs.
In: E. Dietrich (Ed.): 'Thinking Computers and Virtual Persons '.
Academic Press.

@

Coleman, S.

(2000):
Thought experiments and personal identity.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 98, pp. 51-66.

@

Coles, L. S.

(1993):
Engineering machine consciousness.
In: ' AI Expert ', vol. 8, pp. 34-41.

@

Collins, A.

(1992):
On the paradox Kripke finds in Wittgenstein.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 18.

@

Collins, A. W.

(1997):
Personal identity and the coherence of q-memory.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 47, pp. 73-80.

@

Collins, D.

(1988):
Belief, desire, and revision.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 97, pp. 333-42.

@

Collins, J.

(2000):
Theory of mind, logical form and eliminativism.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 13, pp. 465-490.

@

Collins, J.

(2003):
Cowie on the poverty of stimulus.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 136, pp. 159-190.

@

Collins, J.

(2005):
Faculty disputes.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 19, pp. 503-33.

@

Collins, J.

(2005):
On the input problem for massive modularity.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 15, pp. 1-22.

@

Coltheart, M.; Davies, M.

(2000):
Pathologies of Belief.
Blackwell.

@

Combes, R.

(1988):
Ockhamite reductionism.
In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 28, pp. 325-36.

@

Conee, E.

(1984):
A defense of pain.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 46, pp. 239-48.

@

Cook, K. S.; Levi, M.

(1990):
The Limits of Rationality.
University of Chicago Press.

@

Cooper, W. E.

(1980):
Materialism and madness.
In: ' Philosophical Papers ', vol. 9, pp. 36-40.

@

Copeland, B. J.

(1993):
The curious case of the Chinese gym.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 95, pp. 173-86.

@

Copeland, B. J.

(1996):
What is computation?.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 108, pp. 335-59.

@

Copeland, B. J.

(2000):
The Turing test.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 10, pp. 519-539.

@

Copeland, B. J.

(2000):
Narrow versus wide mechanism: Including a re-examination of Turing's views on the mind-machine issue .
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 97, pp. 5-33.

@

Copeland, B. J.

(2003):
The Chinese room from a logical point of view.
In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Copeland, J.

(2002):
Narrow versus wide mechanism.
In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): 'Computationalism: New Directions '.
MIT Press.

@

Corazza, E.

(1994):
Perspectival thoughts and psychological generalizations.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 48, pp. 307-36.

@

Corazza, E.

(2004):
Reflecting the Mind: Indexicality and Quasi-Indexicality.
Oxford University Press.

@

Corbi, J. E.

(1993):
Classical and connectionist models: Levels of description.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 95, pp. 141-68.

@

Cornman, J.

(1962):
The identity of mind and body.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 59, pp. 486-92.

@

Cornman, J.

(1968):
On the elimination of `sensations' and sensations.
In: ' Review of Metaphysics ', vol. 22, pp. 15-35.

@

Cosmides, L.; Tooby, J.

(1987):
From evolution to behavior: Evolutionary psychology as the missing link.
In: J. Dupre (Ed.): 'The Latest on the Best: Essays on Evolution and Optimality '.
MIT Press.

@

Cosmides, L.; Tooby, J.

(1994):
Beyond intuition and instinct blindness: Toward an evolutionary rigorous cognitive science.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 50, pp. 41-77.

@

Cotterill, R.

(2003):
Cyberchild: A Simulation test-bed for consciousness studies.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 10.

@

Coulter, J.

(1995):
The informed neuron: Issues in the use of information theory in the behavioral sciences.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 5, pp. 583-96.

@

Coulter, J.; Sharrock, S.

(2003):
The hinterland of the Chinese room.
In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Cover, J.; Hawthorne, J.

(1996):
Free agency and materialism.
In: D. Howard-Snyder; J. Jordan (Ed.): 'Faith, Freedom, and Rationality '.
Rowman and Littlefield.

@

Cowan, J.

(1968):
Pleasure and Pain: A Study in Philosophical Psychology.
Macmillan.

@

Cowie, F.

(1997):
The logical problem of language acquisition.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 111, pp. 17-51.

@

Cowie, F.

(1998):
What's Within?.
Oxford University Press.

@

Cowie, F.

(1998):
Mad dog nativism.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 49, pp. 227-252.

@

Cowie, F.

(2001):
On cussing in church: in defense of What's Within?.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 16, pp. 231-245.

@

Cowley, F.

(1971):
The identity of a person and his body.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 68, pp. 678-683.

@

Cozzo, C.

(2002):
Does epistemological holism lead to meaning holism?.
In: ' Topoi ', vol. 21, pp. 25-45.

@

Craig, E.

(1997):
Meaning and privacy.
In: B. Hale; C. Wright (Ed.): 'A Companion to the Philosophy of Language '.
Blackwell.

@

Cram, H-R.

(1992):
Fodor's causal theory of representation.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 42, pp. 56-70.

@

Crane, T.

(1990):
The language of thought: No syntax without semantics.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 5, pp. 187-213.

@

Crane, T.

(1990):
On an alleged analogy between numbers and propositions.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 50, pp. 224-30.

@

Crane, T.

(1991):
All the difference in the world.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 41, pp. 1-25.

@

Crane, T.

(1991):
Why indeed? Papineau on supervenience.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 51, pp. 32-7.

@

Crane, T.

(1991):
All God has to do.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 51, pp. 235-44.

@

Crane, T.

(1992):
Mental causation and mental reality.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 66, pp. 185-202.

@

Crane, T.

(1993):
A definition of physicalism: Reply to Pettit.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 53, pp. 224-27.

@

Crane, T.

(1995):
The mental causation debate (Mental causation I).
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 69, pp. 211-36.

@

Crane, T.

(1998):
Intentionality as the mark of the mental.
In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Crane, T.

(2001):
Intentional objects.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 14, pp. 298-317.

@

Crane, T.

(2001):
The significance of emergence.
In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Crane, T.

(2001):
Jacob on mental causation.
In: ' Acta Analytica ', vol. 16, pp. 15-21.

@

Crane, T.

(2001):
Elements of Mind: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind.
Oxford University Press.

@

Crane, T.

(2003):
Mental substances.
In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Minds and Persons '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Crane, T.

(2003):
The Mechanical Mind: A Philosophical Introduction to Minds, Machines, and Mental Representation.
Routledge.

@

Crane, T.; Mellor, D. H.

(1990):
There is no question of physicalism.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 99, pp. 185-206.

@

Craver, C. F.

(2002):
Interlevel experiments and multilevel mechanisms in the neuroscience of memory.
In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplemental Volume ', vol. 69.

@

Craver, C. F.

(2003):
The making of a memory mechanism.
In: ' Journal of the History of Biology ', vol. 36, pp. 153-95.

@

Craver, C. F; Darden, L.

(2001):
Discovering mechanisms in neurobiology: The case of spatial memory. In (P. K. Machamer, R. Grush, and P .
In: ' 2001 '.

@

Crawford, C.

(1994):
Notes on the Turing test.
In: ' Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery ', vol. 37, pp. 13-15.

@

Crimmins, M.

(1992):
Tacitness and virtual beliefs.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 7, pp. 240-63.

@

Crimmins, M.

(2002):
Talk about Beliefs.
MIT Press.

@

Crisp, R.

(1996):
Evolution and psychological unity.
In: M. Bekoff; D. Jamieson (Ed.): 'Readings in Animal Cognition '.
MIT Press.

@

Crisp, T.; Warfield, T.

(2000):
The irrelevance of indeterministic counterexamples to principle beta.
In: ' Philosophy & Phenomenological Research ', vol. 61, pp. 173-185.

@

Crittenden, C.

(1971):
Ontology and mind-body identity.
In: ' Philosophical Forum ', vol. 2, pp. 251-70.

@

Crockett, L.

(1994):
The Turing Test and the Frame Problem: AI's Mistaken Understanding of Intelligence.
Ablex.

@

Crook, S.

(2001):
Why physics alone cannot define the 'physical': Materialism, metaphysics, and the formulation of physicalism .
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 31, pp. 333-360.

@

Crooks, M.

(2002):
Intertheoretic identification and mind-brain reductionism.
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 23, pp. 193-222.

@

Cruse, H.

(2001):
The explanatory power and limits of simulation models in the neurosciences.
In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences '.
University of Pittsburgh Press.

@

Cruz, J. L. H.

(1998):
Mindreading: Mental state ascription and cognitive architecture.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp. 323-340.

@

Cummins, D. D.

(1996):
Evidence for the innateness of deontic reasoning.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp. 160-90.

@

Cummins, D. D.; Cummins, R.

(1999):
Biological preparedness and evolutionary explanation.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 73.

@

Cummins, R.

(1975):
Functional analysis.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 72, pp. 741-64.

@

Cummins, R.

(1977):
Programs in the explanation of behavior.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 44, pp. 269-87.

@

Cummins, R.

(1981):
What can be learned from Brainstorms?.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 12, pp. 83-92.

@

Cummins, R.

(1982):
The internal manual model of psychological explanation.
In: ' Cognition and Brain Theory ', vol. 5, pp. 257-68.

@

Cummins, R.

(1983):
The Nature of Psychological Explanation.
MIT Press.

@

Cummins, R.

(1986):
Inexplicit information.
In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): 'The Representation of Knowledge and Belief '.
University of Arizona Press.

@

Cummins, R.

(1989):
Representation and covariation.
In: S. Silvers (Ed.): 'ReRepresentation '.
Kluwer.

@

Cummins, R.

(1989):
Meaning and Mental Representation.
MIT Press.

@

Cummins, R.

(1991):
Methodological reflections on belief.
In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): 'Mind and Common Sense '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Cummins, R.

(1991):
Mental meaning in psychological explanation.
In: B. McLaughlin (Ed.): 'Dretske and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Cummins, R.

(1991):
Form, interpretation, and the uniqueness of content: A response to Morris.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp. 31-42.

@

Cummins, R.

(1991):
The role of representation in connectionist explanation of cognitive capacities.
In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Cummins, R.

(1992):
Conceptual role semantics and the explanatory role of content.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 65, pp. 103-127.

@

Cummins, R.

(1995):
Connectionist and the rationale constraint on cognitive explanations.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 9, pp. 105-25.

@

Cummins, R.

(1996):
Representations, Targets, and Attitudes.
MIT Press.

@

Cummins, R.

(1996):
Why there is no symbol grounding problem?.
In: ' Representations, Targets, and Attitudes '.

@

Cummins, R.

(1996):
Systematicity.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 93, pp. 591-614.

@

Cummins, R.

(1997):
The LOT of the causal theory of mental content.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 94, pp. 535-542.

@

Cummins, R.

(2002):
Haugeland on representation and intentionality.
In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Mental Representation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Cummins, R.; Poirier, P.

(2004):
Representation and indication.
In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Representation in Mind '.
Elsevier.

@

Cummins, R.; Schwarz, G.

(1987):
Radical connectionism.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement ', vol. 26, pp. 43-61.

@

Cummins, R.; Schwarz, G.

(1991):
Connectionism, computation, and cognition.
In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind '.
Kluwer.

@

Cunningham, S.

(2000):
What Is a Mind?: An Integrative Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind.
Hackett.

@

Curley, E. M.

(1975):
Dreaming and conceptual revision.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 53, pp. 119-41.

@

Currie, G.

(1984):
Individualism and global supervenience.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 35, pp. 345-58.

@

Currie, G.

(1995):
Visual imagery as the simulation of vision.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 10, pp. 25-44.

@

Currie, G.

(1995):
Imagination as simulation: Aesthetics meets cognitive science.
In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation '.
Blackwell.

@

Currie, G.

(1996):
Simulation-theory, theory-theory, and the evidence from autism.
In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Currie, G.

(1998):
Pretence, pretending, and metarepresenting.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp. 35-55.

@

Currie, G.

(2000):
Imagination, delusion and hallucinations.
In: M. Coltheart; M. Davies (Ed.): 'Pathologies of Belief '.
Blackwell.

@

Currie, G.

(2002):
Desire in imagination.
In: T. Gendler; J. Hawthorne (Ed.): 'Conceivability and Possibility '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Currie, G.

(2002):
Imagination as motivation.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 102, pp. 201-16.

@

Currie, G.; Jureidini, J.

(2001):
Delusion, rationality, empathy.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology ', vol. 8, pp. 159-62.

@

Currie, G.; Ravenscroft, I.

(1997):
Mental simulation and motor imagery.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 64, pp. 161-80.

@

Currie, G.; Ravenscroft, I.

(2002):
Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology.
Oxford University Press.

@

Currie, G.; Ravenscroft, I.

(2002):
Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology.
Oxford University Press.

@

Currie, G.; Sterelny, K.

(2000):
How to think about the modularity of mind-reading.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 50, pp. 145-160.

@

Curzer, H.

(1991):
An ambiguity in Parfit's theory of personal identity.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 4, pp. 16-24.

@

Cussins, A.

(1990):
The connectionist construction of concepts.
In: M. Boden (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of AI '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Cussins, A.

(1990):
The connectionist construction of concepts.
In: M. Boden (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of AI '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Cussins, A.

(1992):
Content, embodiment, and objectivity: The theory of cognitive trails.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 101, pp. 651-88.

@

D'Aquili, E. G.; Newberg, A. B.

(1996):
Consciousness and the machine.
In: ' Zygon ', vol. 31, pp. 235-52.

@

D'Arms, J.; Jacobson, D.

(2000):
The moralistic fallacy: On the "appropriateness" of emotions.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 61, pp. 65-90.

@

Dainton, B.

(1996):
Survival and experience.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 96, pp. 17-36.

@

Dainton, B.

(2004):
The self and the phenomenal.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 17, pp. 365-89.

@

Dalenoort, G. J.

(1990):
Toward a general theory of representation.
In: ' Psychological Research ', vol. 52, pp. 229-237.

@

Dalrymple, H.

(1977):
Some logical muddles in behaviorism.
In: ' Southwestern Philosophical Studies ', vol. 2, pp. 64-72.

@

Daly, C.

(1995):
Does physicalism need fixing?.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 55, pp. 135-41.

@

Daly, C.

(1998):
What are physical properties?.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 79, pp. 196-217.

@

Damasio, A.

(1994):
Descartes' Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain.
Putnam.

@

Damasio, A.

(1999):
The Feeling of what Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness.
Harcourt Brace and Co.

@

Dancy, J. (ed).

(1997):
Reading Parfit.
Blackwell.

@

Daniel, S. G.

(1999):
Why even Kim-style psychophysical laws are impossible.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 80, pp. 225-237.

@

Danto, A.

(1960):
On consciousness in machines.
In: S. Hook (Ed.): 'Dimensions of Mind '.
New York University Press.

@

Dartnall, T.

(2001):
The pain problem.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 14, pp. 95-102.

@

Dartnall, T.

(2005):
Does the world leak into the mind? Active externalism, "internalism", and epistemology.
In: ' Cognitive Science ', vol. 29, pp. 135-43.

@

Dascal, M.

(1992):
Why does language matter to artificial intelligence?.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 2, pp. 145-174.

@

Daugman, J. G.

(2001):
Brain metaphor and brain theory.
In: W. Bechtel; P. Mandik; J. Mundale; and R. Stufflebeam (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader '.
Blackwell.

@

David, M.

(1997):
Kim's functionalism.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 11, pp. 133-48.

@

Davidson, D.

(1970):
Mental events.
In: L. Foster; J. Swanson (Ed.): 'Experience and Theory '.
Humanities Press.

@

Davidson, D.

(1973):
The material mind.
In: P. Suppes (Ed.): 'Logic, Methodology and the Philosophy of Science '.
North-Holland.

@

Davidson, D.

(1973):
Freedom to act.
In: T. Honderich (Ed.): 'Essays on Freedom of Action '.
Routledge.

@

Davidson, D.

(1974):
Psychology as philosophy.
In: S. Brown (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Psychology '.
Harper & Row.

@

Davidson, D.

(1980):
Essays on Actions and Events.
Oxford University Press.

@

Davidson, D.

(1982):
Rational animals.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 36, pp. 317-28.

@

Davidson, D.

(1984):
First person authority.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 38.

@

Davidson, D.

(1985):
Incoherence and irrationality.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 39, pp. 345-54.

@

Davidson, D.

(1987):
Knowing one's own mind.
In: ' 1987 '.

@

Davidson, D.

(1987):
Problems in the explanation of action.
In: P. Pettit; R. Sylvan; J. Norman (Ed.): 'Metaphysics and Morality '.
Blackwell.

@

Davidson, D.

(1990):
Turing's test.
In: K. Said (Ed.): 'Modelling the Mind '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Davidson, D.

(1992):
The second person.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 17.

@

Davidson, D.

(1992):
Thinking causes.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Davidson, D.

(1995):
Laws and cause.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 49, pp. 263-79.

@

Davidson, D.

(1995):
Could there be a science of rationality?.
In: ' International Journal of Philosophical Studies ', vol. 3, pp. 1-16.

@

Davidson, D.

(1999):
The emergence of thought.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 51, pp. 511-21.

@

Davies, D.

(1995):
Dennett's stance on intentional realism.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 33, pp. 299-312.

@

Davies, D.

(1995):
Davidson, indeterminacy, and measurement.
In: ' Acta Analytica ', vol. 10, pp. 37-56.

@

Davies, D.

(1998):
On gauging attitudes.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 90, pp. 129-54.

@

Davies, F.

(1998):
How sceptical is Kripke's "sceptical solution".
In: ' Philsophia ', vol. 26, pp. 119-40.

@

Davies, M.

(1986):
Externality, psychological explanation, and narrow content.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 60, pp. 263-83.

@

Davies, M.

(1986):
Tacit knowledge and the structure of thought and language.
In: C. Travis (Ed.): 'Meaning and Interpretation '.
Blackwell.

@

Davies, M.

(1989):
Connectionism, modularity, and tacit knowledge.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 40, pp. 541-55.

@

Davies, M.

(1989):
Connectionism, modularity and tacit knowledge.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 40, pp. 541-55.

@

Davies, M.

(1989):
Tacit knowledge and subdoxastic states.
In: A. George (Ed.): 'Reflections on Chomsky '.
Blackwell.

@

Davies, M.

(1991):
Individualism and perceptual content.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 100, pp. 461-84.

@

Davies, M.

(1991):
Concepts, connectionism, and the language of thought. (W. Ramsey, S. Stich, & D. Rumelhart, eds) Philosophy and Connectionist Theory .
In: ' 1991 '.

@

Davies, M.

(1992):
Aunty's own argument for the language of thought.
In: J. Ezquerro; J. Larrazabal (Ed.): 'Cognition, Semantics and Philosophy '.
Kluwer.

@

Davies, M.

(1992):
The mental simulation debate.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Truth and Rationality '.
Ridgeview.

@

Davies, M.

(1995):
Two notions of implicit rules.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 9, pp. 153-83.

@

Davies, M.

(1998):
Externalism, architecturalism, and epistemic warrant.
In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Davies, M.

(2000):
Externalism and armchair knowledge.
In: P. Boghossian; C. Peacocke (Ed.): 'New Essays on the A Priori '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Davies, M.

(2003):
Externalism, self-Knowledge and transmission of warrant.
In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind '.
CSLI.

@

Davies, M.

(2003):
The problem of armchair knowledge.
In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge '.
MIT Press.

@

Davies, M.

(2004):
Reference, contingency, and the two-dimensional framework.
In: ' Philosophical Studies, ', vol. 118, pp. 83-131.

@

Davies, M.; Coltheart, M.; Langdon, R. and Breen, N.

(2001):
Monothematic delusions: Towards a two-factor account.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology ', vol. 8, pp. 133-58.

@

Davies, M.; Davies, A. A.; Coltheart, M.

(2005):
Anosognosia and the two-factor theory of delusions.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 20, pp. 241-57.

@

Davies, M.; Humphreys, G.

(1993):
Consciousness: Philosophical and Psychological Essays.
Blackwell.

@

Davies, M.; Stone, T.

(1995):
Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications.
Blackwell.

@

Davies, M.; Stone, T.

(1995):
Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate.
Blackwell.

@

Davies, M.; Stone, T.

(2001):
Mental simulation, tacit theory, and the threat of collapse.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 29, pp. 127-73.

@

Davies, P. S.

(1999):
The conflict of evolutionary psychology.
In: V. Hardcastle (Ed.): 'Where Biology Meets Psychology '.
MIT Press.

@

Davies, S.

(1988):
Kripke, Crusoe and Wittgenstein.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 66.

@

Davis, L.

(1997):
Cerebral hemispheres.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 87, pp. 207-22.

@

Davis, L. H.

(1998):
Functionalism and personal identity.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 58, pp. 781-804.

@

Davis, L. H.

(2001):
Functionalism, the brain, and personal identity.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 102, pp. 259-79.

@

Davis, S.

(2003):
Arguments for externalism.
In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind '.
CSLI.

@

Davis, W.

(1981):
A theory of happiness.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 18, pp. 111-20.

@

Davis, W.

(1986):
Two senses of desire.
In: J. Marks (Ed.): 'The Ways of Desire '.
Precedent.

@

Davis, W. A.

(2005):
Concept individuation, possession conditions, and propositional attitudes.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 39, pp. 140-66.

@

Daw, R.; Alter, T.

(2001):
Free acts and robot cats.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 102, pp. 345-57.

@

Dawkins, M. S.

(1987):
Minding and mattering.
In: C. Blakemore; S. Greenfield (Ed.): 'Mindwaves '.
Blackwell.

@

Dawkins, M. S.

(1990):
From an animal's point of view: Motivation, fitness, and animal welfare.
In: ' 1990 '.

@

Dawson, M. R. W.; Medler, D. A.; Berkeley, I. S. N.

(1997):
PDP networks can provide models that are not mere implementations of classical theories.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 10, pp. 25-40.

@

Dawson, M. R. W.; Schopflocher, D. P.

(1992):
Autonomous processing in parallel distributed processing networks.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 5, pp. 199-219.

@

De Anna, G.

(2002):
The simple view of colour and the reference of perceptual terms.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 77, pp. 87-108.

@

De Rosa, R.

(2000):
On Fodor's claim that classical empiricists and rationalists agree on the innateness of ideas.
In: ' Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp. 240-269.

@

DeLancey, C.

(1996):
Emotion and the function of consciousness.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 3, pp. 492-99.

@

DeLancey, C.

(1997):
Emotion and the computational theory of mind.
In: S. O'Nuillain; P. McKevitt; E. MacAogain (Ed.): 'Two Sciences of Mind '.
John Benjamins.

@

DeLancey, C.

(1998):
Real emotions.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 11, pp. 467-487.

@

DeLancey, C.

(2001):
Passionate Engines: What Emotions Reveal about the Mind and Artificial Intelligence.
Oxford University Press.

@

DeWitt, R.

(1995):
Vagueness, semantics, and the language of thought.
In: ' Psyche ', vol. 1.

@

Decety, J.

(2002):
Neurophysiological evidence for simulation and action.
In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action '.
John Benjamins.

@

Dedrick, D.

(1995):
Objectivism and the evolutionary value of color vision.
In: ' Dialogue ', vol. 34, pp. 35-44.

@

Dedrick, D.

(1996):
Can color be reduced to anything?.
In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement ', vol. 3, pp. 134-42.

@

Degrazia, D.

(2002):
Are we essentially persons? Olson, Baker, and a reply.
In: ' Philosophical Forum ', vol. 33, pp. 81-99.

@

Deigh, J.

(1994):
Cognitivism in the theory of emotions.
In: ' Ethics ', vol. 104, pp. 824-54.

@

Deigh, J.

(2004):
Primitive emotions.
In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Demopoulos, W.

(1987):
On some fundamental distinctions of computationalism.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 70, pp. 79-96.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1968):
The nature of images and the introspective trap.
In: ' Content and Consciousness '.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1971):
Intentional systems.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 68, pp. 87-106.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1975):
Brain writing and mind reading.
In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 7, pp. 403-15.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1976):
Conditions of personhood.Lewis, D. 1976.
In: A. Rorty (Ed.): 'The Identities of Persons '.
University of California Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1976):
Are dreams experiences?.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 73, pp. 151-71.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1977):
A cure for the common code.
In: ' 1977 '.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978):
Brainstorms.
MIT Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978):
Where am I?.
In: ' Brainstorms '.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978):
On giving libertarians what they say they want.
In: ' Brainstorms '.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978):
The abilities of men and machines.
In: ' Brainstorms '.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978):
AI as philosophy and as psychology.
In: M. Ringle (Ed.): 'Philosophical Perspectives on Artificial Intelligence '.
Humanities Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978):
Why you can't make a computer that feels pain.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 38.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978):
Two approaches to mental images.
In: ' Brainstorms '.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978):
Current issues in the philosophy of mind.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 15, pp. 249-261.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1981):
Making sense of ourselves.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 12, pp. 63-81.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1983):
Beyond belief.
In: A. Woodfield (Ed.): 'Thought and Object '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1983):
Beyond belief.
In: A. Woodfield (Ed.): 'Thought and Object '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1983):
Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: The `Panglossian paradigm' defended.
In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences ', vol. 6, pp. 343-90.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1984):
Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting.
MIT Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1984):
Can machines think?.
In: M. Shafto (Ed.): 'How We Know '.
Harper & Row.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1984):
Cognitive wheels: The frame problem of AI.
In: Hookaway (Ed.): 'Minds, Machines and Evolution '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1985):
Can machines think?.
In: ' How We Know '.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1986):
The logical geography of computational approaches: A view from the east pole.
In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): 'The Representation of Knowledge and Belief '.
University of Arizona Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1987):
The Intentional Stance.
MIT Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1987):
Fast thinking.
In: ' The Intentional Stance '.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1988):
Precis of The Intentional Stance.
In: ' 1988 '.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1988):
Fear of Darwin's optimizing rationale.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1988):
Evolution, error and intentionality.
In: ' The Intentional Stance '.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1989):
The origins of selves.
In: ' Cogito ', vol. 3, pp. 163-73.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1989):
Cognitive ethology: Hunting for bargains or a wild goose chase?.
In: Montefiore (Ed.): 'Goals, No-Goals and Own Goals '.
Unwin Hyman.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1990):
Granny's campaign for safe science.
In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1990):
The interpretation of texts, people and other artifacts.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (Supplement) ', vol. 50.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1991):
Real patterns.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 88, pp. 27-51.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1991):
Ways of establishing harmony.
In: B. McLaughlin (Ed.): 'Dretske and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1991):
Mother Nature versus the walking encyclopedia.
In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1991):
Two contrasts: Folk craft vs folk science and belief vs opinion.
In: J. Greenwood (Ed.): 'The Future of Folk Psychology '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1994):
The practical requirements for making a conscious robot.
In: ' Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A ', vol. 349, pp. 133-46.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1995):
Cog: Steps toward consciousness in robots.
In: T. Metzinger (Ed.): 'Conscious Experience '.
Ferdinand Schoningh.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1995):
Do animals have beliefs?.
In: H. Roitblat; J. Meyer (Ed.): 'Comparative Approaches to Cognitive Science '.
MIT Press.

@

Dennett, D. C.

(1996):
Kinds of Minds.
Basic Books.

@

DesAutels, P.

(1995):
Two types of theories: The impact of Churchland's perceptual plasticity.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 8, pp. 25-33.

@

Deutscher, M.

(1989):
Remembering "Remembering".
In: J. Heil (Ed.): 'Identity, Cause, and Mind '.
Kluwer.

@

Devitt, M.

(1990):
Meanings just ain't in the head.
In: G. Boolos (Ed.): 'Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Devitt, M.

(1990):
The narrow representational theory of mind.
In: W. Lycan (Ed.): 'Mind and Cognition '.
Blackwell.

@

Devitt, M.

(1990):
Transcendentalism about content.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 71, pp. 247-63.

@

Devitt, M.

(1991):
Why Fodor can't have it both ways.
In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Devitt, M.

(1994):
The methodology of naturalistic semantics.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 91, pp. 519-44.

@

Devitt, M.

(1994):
A critique of the case for semantic holism.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 8, pp. 281-306.

@

Devitt, M.

(1994):
Semantic localism: Who needs a principled basis?.
In: R. Casati; B. Smith; S. White (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences '.
Holder-Pichler-Tempsky.

@

Devitt, M.

(2001):
A shocking idea about meaning.
In: ' Revue Internationale de Philosophie ', vol. 55, pp. 471-494.

@

Devitt, M.; Rey, G.

(1991):
Transcending transcendentalism.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 72, pp. 87-100.

@

Diamond, C.

(1989):
Rules: Looking in the right place. In (D. Phillips & P.
In: ' 1989 '.

@

Dietrich, E.

(1988):
Computers, intentionality, and the new dualism.

@

Dietrich, E.

(1989):
Semantics and the computational paradigm in computational psychology.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 79, pp. 119-41.

@

Dietrich, E.

(1990):
Computationalism.
In: ' 1990 '.

@

Dietrich, E.; Markman, A.

(2003):
Discrete thoughts: Why cognition must use discrete representations.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 18, pp. 95-119.

@

Dilman, I.

(1999):
Free Will: An Historical and Philosophical Introduction.
Routledge.

@

Dinsmore, J.

(1992):
The Symbolic and Connectionist Paradigms: Closing the Gap.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Divers, J.

(1996):
Supervenience for operators.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 106, pp. 103-12.

@

Dodwell, P.

(2000):
Brave New Mind: A Thoughtful Inquiry into the Nature and Meaning of Mental Life.
Oxford University Press.

@

Doepke, F.

(1990):
The practical importance of personal identity.
In: ' Logos ', vol. 83.

@

Dokic, J.

(2002):
Reply to 'The scope and limit of mental simulation'.
In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action '.
John Benjamins.

@

Dokic, J.; Proust, J.

(2002):
Simulation and Knowledge of Action.
John Benjamins.

@

Dokic, Jerome,

(2001):
Is memory purely preservative?.
In: C. Hoerl; . T. McCormack (Ed.): 'Time and Memory '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Donovan, C.

(1978):
Eliminative materialism reconsidered.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 8.

@

Doppelt, G.

(1977):
Incorrigibility, the mental, and materialism.
In: ' 1977 '.

@

Dorschel, A.

(2002):
The authority of the will.
In: ' The Philosophical Forum ', vol. 33, pp. 425-442.

@

Double, R.

(1981):
Central state materialism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies (Ireland) ', vol. 28, pp. 229-37.

@

Double, R.

(1983):
Searle, programs and functionalism.
In: ' Nature and System ', vol. 5, pp. 107-14.

@

Double, R.

(1987):
The computational model of the mind and philosophical functionalism.
In: ' Behaviorism ', vol. 15, pp. 131-39.

@

Double, R.

(1989):
Puppeteers, hypnotists, and neurosurgeons.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 56, pp. 163-73.

@

Double, R.

(1991):
The Non-Reality of Free Will.
Oxford University Press.

@

Double, R.

(1991):
Determinism and the experience of freedom.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 72, pp. 1-8.

@

Double, R.

(1992):
How rational must free will be?.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 23, pp. 268-78.

@

Double, R.

(1994):
How to frame the free will problem.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 75, pp. 149-72.

@

Double, R.

(1996):
Metaphilosophy and Free Will.
Oxford University Press.

@

Double, R.

(1997):
Misdirection on the free will problem.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 34, pp. 359-68.

@

Double, R.

(1999):
In defense of the smart aleck: A reply to Ted Honderich.
In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research ', vol. 24, pp. 305-9.

@

Double, R.

(2002):
Metaethics, metaphilosophy, and free will subjectivism.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Double, R.

(2002):
Metaethics, metaphilosophy and free will subjectivism.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Double, R.

(2004):
The ethical advantages of free will subjectivism.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 69.

@

Douglas, G.

(1998):
Why pains are not mental objects.
In: ' Philosophical Studies b ', vol. 91, pp. 127-148.

@

Downes, S.

(2002):
Some recent developments in evolutionary approaches to the study of human cognition and behavior.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 16, pp. 575-94.

@

Drai, D.

(2003):
Externalism without identity.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 134, pp. 463-75.

@

Dreckmann, F.

(1999):
Animal beliefs and their contents.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 51, pp. 597-615.

@

Dretske, F.

(1973):
Perception and other minds.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 7, pp. 34-44.

@

Dretske, F.

(1981):
Knowledge and the Flow of Information.
MIT Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(1983):
Precis of Knowledge and the Flow of Information.
In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences ', vol. 6, pp. 55-90.

@

Dretske, F.

(1985):
Machines and the mental.
In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association ', vol. 59, pp. 23-33.

@

Dretske, F.

(1985):
Machines and the mental.
In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association ', vol. 59, pp. 23-33.

@

Dretske, F.

(1986):
Misrepresentation.
In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): 'Belief: Form, Content, and Function '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(1986):
Aspects of cognitive representation.
In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): 'The Representation of Knowledge and Belief '.
University of Arizona Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(1987):
The explanatory role of content.
In: R. Grimm; D. Merrill (Ed.): 'Contents of Thought '.
University of Arizona Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(1988):
Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes.
MIT Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(1990):
Putting information to work.
In: P. Hanson (Ed.): 'Information, Language and Cognition '.
University of British Columbia Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(1990):
Does meaning matter?.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Information, Semantics, and Epistemology '.
Blackwell.

@

Dretske, F.

(1992):
What isn't wrong with folk psychology.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 23, pp. 1-13.

@

Dretske, F.

(1993):
The nature of thought.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 70, pp. 185-99.

@

Dretske, F.

(1993):
Mental events as structuring causes of behavior.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(1993):
Can intelligence be artificial?.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 71, pp. 201-16.

@

Dretske, F.

(1994):
Reply to Slater and Garcia-Carpintero.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 9, pp. 203-8.

@

Dretske, F.

(1995):
Reply: Causal relevance and explanatory exclusion.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Information, Semantics, and Epistemology '.
Blackwell.

@

Dretske, F.

(1996):
The explanatory role of content: Reply to Melnyk and Noordhof.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp. 223-29.

@

Dretske, F.

(2000):
Perception, Knowledge and Belief: Selected Essays.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(2001):
Where is the mind?.
In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Explaining Beliefs '.
CSLI.

@

Dretske, F.

(2001):
Norms, history, and the mental.
In: D. Walsh (Ed.): 'Evolution, Naturalism and Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(2003):
Externalism and self-knowledge.
In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge '.
MIT Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(2003):
Burge on mentalistic explanations, or why I am still epiphobic.
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Dretske, F.

(2004):
Psychological vs. biological explanations of behavior.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 32, pp. 167-177.

@

Dreyfus, H. L.

(1972):
What Computers Can't Do.
Harper and Row.

@

Dreyfus, H. L.

(1979):
A framework for misrepresenting knowledge.
In: M. Ringle (Ed.): 'Philosophical Perspectives in Artificial Intelligence '.
Humanities Press.

@

Dreyfus, H. L.

(1981):
From micro-worlds to knowledge: AI at an impasse.
In: J. Haugeland (Ed.): 'Mind Design '.
MIT Press.

@

Dreyfus, H. L.; Dreyfus, S.

(1987):
How to stop worrying about the frame problem even though it's computationally insoluble.
In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): 'The Robot's Dilemma '.
Ablex.

@

Dreyfus, H. L.; Dreyfus, S. E.

(1988):
Making a mind versus modeling the brain: AI at a crossroads.
In: ' 1988 '.

@

Drozdek, A.

(2001):
Descartes' Turing test.
In: ' Epistemologia ', vol. 24, pp. 5-29.

@

Duggan, T.; Gert, B.

(1979):
Free will as the ability to will.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 13, pp. 197-217.

@

Duhrssen, A.

(1963):
Philosophic alienation and the problem of other minds.
In: ' 1963 '.

@

Dunlop, C. E. M.

(1977):
Philosophical Essays on Dreaming.
Cornell University Press.

@

Dunlop, C. E. M.

(1978):
Belief in dreams.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 56, pp. 61-64.

@

Dunlop, C. E. M.

(1978):
Dreams, skepticism, and scientific research.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 8, pp. 355-65.

@

Dunlop, C. E. M.

(1990):
Conceptual dependency as the language of thought.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 82, pp. 275-96.

@

Dunlop, C. E. M.

(2004):
Mentalese semantics and the naturalized mind.
In: ' Philosphical Psychology ', vol. 17, pp. 77-94.

@

Dupre, J.

(1988):
Materialism, physicalism, and scientism.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 16, pp. 31-56.

@

Dupre, J.

(1996):
The solution to the problem of freedom of the will.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 10, pp. 385-402.

@

Dupre, J.

(1996):
The mental lives of nonhuman animals.
In: M. Bekoff; D. Jamieson (Ed.): 'Readings in Animal Cognition '.
MIT Press.

@

Dupuy, J.

(2000):
The Mechanization of the Mind: On the Origins of Cognitive Science.
Princeton University Press.

@

Dworkin, G.

(1970):
Acting freely.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 4, pp. 367-83.

@

Dworkin, G.

(1970):
Determinism, Free Will, and Moral Responsibility.
Prentice-Hall.

@

Dwyer, P.

(1989):
Freedom and rule-following in Wittgenstein and Sartre.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 50, pp. 49-68.

@

Dyer, M.

(1990):
Intentionality and computationalism: minds, machines, Searle and Harnad.
In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 2, pp. 303-19.

@

Dyer, M.

(1990):
Finding lost minds.
In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 2, pp. 329-39.

@

Dyer, M.

(1991):
Connectionism versus symbolism in high-level cognition.
In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind '.
Kluwer.

@

Earle, W.

(1956):
Memory.
In: ' Review of Metaphysics ', vol. 10, pp. 3-27.

@

Ebbs, G.

(1996):
Can we take our words at face value?.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 56, pp. 499-530.

@

Ebbs, G.

(1997):
Rule-Following and Realism.
Harvard University Press.

@

Ebbs, G.

(2001):
Is skepticism about self-knowledge coherent?.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 105, pp. 43-58.

@

Ebbs, G.

(2003):
A puzzle about doubt.
In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge '.
MIT Press.

@

Eccles, J.

(1976):
Brain and free will.
In: G. Globus (Ed.): 'Consciousness and the Brain '.
Plenum Press.

@

Eckardt, von, B.

(1984):
Cognitive psychology and principled skepticism.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 81, pp. 67-88.

@

Eckardt, von, B.

(1993):
What is Cognitive Science?.
MIT Press.

@

Eckardt, von, B.

(1997):
The empirical naivete in the current philosophical conception of folk psychology.
In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind '.
Pittsburgh University Press.

@

Eckardt, von, B.

(2003):
The explanatory need for mental representations in cognitive science.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 3, no. 18, pp. 427-439..

@

Edis, T.

(1998):
How Godel's theorem supports the possibility of machine intelligence.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 8, pp. 251-262.

@

Edwards, J.

(1998):
The simple theory of colour and the transparency of sense experience.
In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Edwards, J.

(1999):
Interpreted logical forms and knowing your own mind.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 99, pp. 169-90.

@

Edwards, J.

(2003):
A reply to De Anna on the simple view of colour.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 78, pp. 99-114.

@

Edwards, R.

(1975):
Do pleasures and pains differ qualitatively?.
In: ' Journal of Value Inquiry ', vol. 9, pp. 270-81.

@

Edwards, S.

(1994):
Externalism in the Philosophy of Mind.
Avebury.

@

Efron, A.

(1992):
Residual asymmetric dualism: A theory of mind-body relations.
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 13, pp. 113-36.

@

Egan, F.

(1991):
Must psychology be individualistic?.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 100, pp. 179-203.

@

Egan, F.

(1992):
Individualism, computation, and perceptual content.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 101, pp. 443-59.

@

Egan, F.

(1995):
Computation and content.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 104, pp. 181-203.

@

Egan, F.

(1995):
Folk psychology and cognitive architecture.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 62, pp. 179-96.

@

Egan, F.

(1996):
Intentionality and the theory of vision.
In: K. Akins (Ed.): 'Perception '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Egan, F.

(1999):
In defence of narrow mindedness.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 14, pp. 177-94.

@

Egan, M. F.

(1989):
What's wrong with the Syntactic Theory of Mind.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 56, pp. 664-74.

@

Egan, M. F.

(1991):
Propositional attitudes and the language of thought.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 21, pp. 379-88.

@

Ehring, D.

(1987):
Survival and trivial facts.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 47, pp. 50-54.

@

Ehring, D.

(1995):
Personal identity and the R-relation: Reconciliation through cohabitation.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 73, pp. 337-346.

@

Ehring, D.

(1996):
Mental causation, determinables, and property instances.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 30, pp. 461-80.

@

Ehring, D.

(1999):
Fission, fusion, and the Parfit revolution.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 94, pp. 329-32.

@

Ehring, D.

(2003):
Part-whole physicalism and mental causation.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 136, pp. 359-388.

@

Eilan, N.

(2005):
Joint attention, communication, and mind. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler, eds) Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds .
In: ' 2005 '.

@

Eilan, N.; Hoerl, C.; McCormack, T.; Roessler, J.

(2005):
Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds.
Oxford University Press.

@

Eklund, M.

(2002):
Personal identity and conceptual incoherence.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 36, pp. 465-485.

@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(1998):
Freedom, causation, and the consequence argument.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 115, pp. 333-54.

@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(1998):
Protecting incompatibilist free action.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 35, pp. 281-91.

@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(2000):
Free Will: A Philosophical Study.
Westview.

@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(2001):
Agency and Responsibility: Essays on the Metaphysics of Freedom.
Westview.

@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(2002):
Libertarianism and Frankfurt-style cases.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(2003):
Free will, chance, and mystery.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 22, pp. 153-80.

@

Elder, C.

(1999):
Physicalism and the fallacy of composition.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 50, pp. 332-43.

@

Elder, C.

(2001):
Mental causation versus physical causation: no contest.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 62, pp. 110-127.

@

Elder, C.

(2001):
Materialism and the mediated causation of behavior.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 103, pp. 165-75.

@

Elder, C.

(2003):
Kripkean externalism versus conceptual analysis.
In: ' Facta Philosophica ', vol. 5, pp. 75-86.

@

Elder, C. L.

(1996):
Content and the subtle extensionality of "... explains ...".
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 46, pp. 320-32.

@

Elder, C. L.

(1998):
What versus how in naturally selected representations.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 107, pp. 349-363.

@

Eldridge, R.

(1986):
The normal and the normative: Wittgenstein's legacy, Kripke, and Cavell.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 46, pp. 555-575.

@

Elgin, C.

(1980):
Indeterminacy, underdetermination and the anomalous monism.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 45, pp. 233-55.

@

Eliasmith, C.

(1996):
The third contender: A critical examination of the dynamicist theory of cognition.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 9, pp. 441-63.

@

Eliasmith, C.

(1997):
Computation and dynamical models of mind.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 7, pp. 531-41.

@

Eliasmith, C.

(2003):
Moving beyond metaphors: Understanding the mind for what it is.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 100, pp. 493-520.

@

Elliot, R.

(1991):
Personal identity and the causal continuity requirement.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 41, pp. 55-75.

@

Ellis, J.

(2005):
Colour irrealism and the formation of colour concepts.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 83, pp. 53-73.

@

Ellis, R.

(2000):
Consciousness, self-organization, and the process-substratum relation: Rethinking nonreductive physicalism .
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 13, pp. 173-190.

@

Ellis, R. D.

(2001):
Can dynamical systems explain mental causation?.
In: ' Journal of Mind And Behavior ', vol. 22, pp. 311-334.

@

Elster, J.

(2004):
Emotion and action.
In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Elugardo, R.

(1981):
Machine functionalism and the New Lilliputian argument.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 62, pp. 256-61.

@

Elugardo, R.

(1983):
Machine realization and the New Lilliputian argument.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 43, pp. 267-75.

@

Elugardo, R.

(1988):
Against weak psychophysical supervenience.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 42, pp. 129-43.

@

Elugardo, R.

(1993):
Burge on content.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 53, pp. 367-84.

@

Emmett, K.

(1978):
Oneiric experiences.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 34, pp. 445-50.

@

Enc, B.

(1983):
In defense of the identity theory.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 80, pp. 279-98.

@

Enc, B.

(1996):
Nonreducible supervenient causation.
In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Endicott, R. P.

(1989):
On physical multiple realization.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 70, pp. 212-24.

@

Endicott, R. P.

(1991):
Macdonald on type reduction via disjunction.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 29, pp. 209-14.

@

Endicott, R. P.

(1993):
Species-specific properties and more narrow reductive strategies.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 38, pp. 303-21.

@

Endicott, R. P.

(1996):
Searle, syntax, and observer-relativity.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 26, pp. 101-22.

@

Endicott, R. P.

(1998):
Collapse of the new wave.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 95, pp. 53-72.

@

Engel, M.

(1993):
The problem of other minds: a reliable solution.
In: ' Acta Analytica ', vol. 11, pp. 87-109.

@

Engel, P.

(1987):
Functionalism, belief, and content.
In: Torrance (Ed.): 'The Mind and the Machine '.
Horwood.

@

Engel, P.

(2000):
Wherein lies the normative dimension in meaning and mental content?.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 100, pp. 305-321.

@

Engel, P.

(2002):
Intentionality, normativity, and community.
In: ' Facta Philosophica ', vol. 4, pp. 25-49.

@

Erion, G. J.

(2001):
The Cartesian test for automatism.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp. 29-39.

@

Erneling, C.

(2004):
The Mind as a Scientific Object: Between Brain and Culture.
Oxford University Press.

@

Esfeld, M.

(1998):
Holism and analytic philosophy.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 107, pp. 365-80.

@

Evans, D.

(2002):
The search hypothesis of emotions.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 53, pp. 497-509.

@

Evans, D.; Cruse, P.

(2004):
Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality.
Oxford University Press.

@

Evans, S.

(1981):
Separable souls: A defense of minimal dualism.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 19.

@

Everett, T.

(2000):
Other voices, other minds.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 78, pp. 213-222.

@

Everitt, N.

(1981):
A problem for the eliminative materialist.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 90, pp. 428-34.

@

Everitt, N.

(1983):
How not to solve a problem for the eliminative materialist.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 92, pp. 590-92.

@

Ewing, A. C.

(1953):
Professor Ryle's attack on dualism.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 53, pp. 47-78.

@

Falk, A.

(1981):
On some modal confusions in compatibilism.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 18, pp. 141-48.

@

Falk, A. E.

(2004):
Desire and Belief: Introduction to Some Recent Philosophical Debates.
Hamilton Books, University Press of America.

@

Falvey, K.

(1999):
A natural history of belief.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 80, pp. 324-345.

@

Falvey, K.

(1999):
A natural history of belief.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 80, pp. 324-345.

@

Falvey, K.

(2000):
The compatibility of anti-individualism and privileged access.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 60, pp. 137-142.

@

Falvey, K.

(2000):
The basis of first-person authority.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 28, pp. 69-99.

@

Falvey, K.

(2003):
Memory and knowledge of content.
In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge '.
MIT Press.

@

Falvey, K.; Owens, J.

(1994):
Externalism, self-knowledge, and skepticism.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 103, pp. 107-37.

@

Farah, M. J.

(1988):
Is visual imagery really visual: Some overlooked evidence from neuropsychology.
In: ' Psychological Review ', vol. 95, pp. 307-17.

@

Farkas, K.

(2003):
What is externalism?.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 112, pp. 187-208.

@

Farrell, B.

(1950):
Experience.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 59, pp. 170-98.

@

Feest, U.

(2003):
Functional analysis and the autonomy of psychology.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 70, pp. 937-948.

@

Feferman, S.

(1996):
Penrose's Godelian argument.
In: ' Psyche ', vol. 2, pp. 21-32.

@

Feigl, H.

(1958):
The `mental' and the `physical'.
In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 2, pp. 370-497.

@

Feigl, H.

(1959):
Other minds and the egocentric predicament.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 56, pp. 980-87.

@

Feigl, H.

(1971):
Some crucial issues of mind-body monism.
In: ' 1971 '.

@

Feldman, R.

(1988):
Rationality, reliability, and natural selection.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 55, pp. 218-27.

@

Fellous, J.

(2004):
Who Needs Emotions: The Brain meets the Robot.
Oxford University Press.

@

Fellows, R.

(2000):
Animal belief.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 75, pp. 587-599.

@

Ferguson, S.

(2002):
Methodology in evolutionary psychology.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 17, pp. 635-50.

@

Fernandez, J.

(2003):
Privileged access naturalized.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 53, pp. 352-372.

@

Fernandez, J.

(2004):
Externalism and self-knowledge: A puzzle in two dimensions.
In: ' European Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 12, pp. 17-37.

@

Fernandez, J.

(2004):
Externalism and self-knowledge: A puzzle in two dimensions.
In: ' European Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 12, pp. 17-37.

@

Fernandez, J.

(2005):
Privileged access revisited.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 55.

@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1990):
The frame problem: Artificial intelligence meets David Hume.
In: ' International Journal of Expert Systems ', vol. 3, pp. 219-232.

@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1990):
Artificial Intelligence: Its Scope and Limits.
Kluwer.

@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1990):
Evolution, rationality and testability.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 82, pp. 423-39.

@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1991):
Philosophy and Cognitive Science.
Paragon House.

@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1992):
Connectionism and cognition: Why Fodor and Pylyshyn are wrong.
In: A. Clark; R. Lutz (Ed.): 'Connectionism in Context '.
Springer-Verlag.

@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1994):
Mental algorithms: Are minds computational systems?.
In: ' Pragmatics and Cognition ', vol. 21, pp. 1-29.

@

Feyerabend, P.

(1963):
Mental events and the brain.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 40, pp. 295-6.

@

Feyerabend, P.

(1963):
Materialism and the mind-body problem.
In: ' Review of Metaphysics ', vol. 17, pp. 49-67.

@

Ficsher, J. M.

(1983):
Incompatibilism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 43, pp. 127-37.

@

Field, H.

(1977):
Logic, meaning, and conceptual role.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 74, pp. 379-409.

@

Field, H.

(1978):
Mental representation.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 13, pp. 9-18.

@

Field, H.

(1978):
Mental representation.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 13, pp. 9-61.

@

Field, H.

(1989):
"Narrow" aspects of intentionality and the information-theoretic approach to content.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Information, Semantics, and Epistemology '.
Blackwell.

@

Fields, C.

(1984):
Double on Searle's Chinese Room.
In: ' Nature and System ', vol. 6, pp. 51-54.

@

Fields, C.

(1994):
Real machines and virtual intentionality: An experimentalist takes on the problem of representational content .
In: E. Dietrich (Ed.): 'Thinking Computers and Virtual Persons '.
Academic Press.

@

Fields, L.

(1987):
Parfit on personal identity and desert.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 37, pp. 432-41.

@

Finch, A.; Warfield, T.

(1998):
The Mind argument and libertarianism.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 107, pp. 515-28.

@

Fine, A.

(1993):
Indeterminism and the freedom of the will.
In: J. Earman (Ed.): 'Philosophical Problems of the Internal and External World '.
University of Pittsburgh Press.

@

Fine, A.

(1996):
Science as child's play: Tales from the crib.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 63, pp. 534-37.

@

Finke, R. A.

(1989):
Principles of Mental Imagery.
MIT Press.

@

Finkelstein, D.

(1999):
On self-blindness and inner sense.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 26, pp. 105-19.

@

Finkelstein, D.

(2003):
Expression and the Inner.
Harvard University Press.

@

Finkelstein, D. H.

(2000):
Wittgenstein on rules and Platonism.
In: A. Crary; R. Read (Ed.): 'The New Wittgenstein '.
Routledge.

@

Finn, D. R.

(1971):
Putnam and logical behaviourism.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 80, pp. 432-36.

@

Fischer, J.

(1985):
Functionalism and propositions.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 48, pp. 295-311.

@

Fischer, J. M.

(1982):
Responsibility and control.
In: ' Journal of Philsophy ', vol. 79, pp. 24-40.

@

Fischer, J. M.

(1994):
The Metaphysics of Free Will: A Study of Control.
Blackwell.

@

Fischer, J. M.

(1996):
A new compatibilism.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 24, pp. 49-66.

@

Fischer, J. M.

(2002):
Frankfurt-type examples and semi-compatibilism.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Fischer, J. M.; Ravizza, M.

(1992):
When the will is free.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 6, pp. 423-51.

@

Fischer, J. M.; Ravizza, M.

(1996):
Free will and the modal principle.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 3, pp. 213-30.

@

Fischer, J. M.; Ravizza, M.

(1998):
Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Fisher, C. M.

(2001):
If there were no free will.
In: ' Medical Hypotheses ', vol. 56, pp. 364-366.

@

Fisher, J.

(1988):
The wrong stuff: Chinese rooms and the nature of understanding.
In: ' Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 11, pp. 279-99.

@

Flanagan, O.

(1994):
Multiple identity, character transformation, and self-reclamation.
In: G. Graham; G. Stephens (Ed.): 'Philosophical Psychopathology '.
MIT Press.

@

Flanagan, O.

(1995):
Deconstructing dreams: The spandrels of sleep.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 92, pp. 5-27.

@

Flanagan, O.

(1996):
Self-expression in sleep: Neuroscience and dreams.
In: ' Self-Expressions '.

@

Flanagan, O.

(2000):
Dreaming Souls: Sleep, Dreams, and the Evolution of the Conscious Mind.
Oxford University Press.

@

Flanagan, O. J.

(1984):
The Science of the Mind.
MIT Press.

@

Flanagan, O. J.

(1991):
Consciousness.
In: ' The Science of the Mind '.

@

Flanagan, O. J.; McCreadie-Albright, T.

(1974):
Malcolm and the fallacy of behaviorism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 26, pp. 425-30.

@

Fletcher, G.

(1995):
The Scientific Credibility of Folk Psychology.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Fletcher, G.

(1995):
Two uses of folk psychology: Implications for psychological science.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 8, pp. 375-88.

@

Flint, T.

(1987):
Compatibilism and the argument from unavoidability.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 84, pp. 423-40.

@

Floridi, L.

(2003):
Two approaches to the philosophy of information.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 13, pp. 459-469.

@

Fodor, J.

(1995):
Concepts: A potboiler. Cognition 50:133-51. Also in (E. Villanueva, ed) Content.
In: ' 1995 '.

@

Fodor, J.

(1997):
Special sciences: Still autonomous after all these years.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 11, pp. 149-63.

@

Fodor, J.

(1998):
Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong.
Oxford University Press.

@

Fodor, J.

(2000):
The Mind Doesn't Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology.
MIT Press.

@

Fodor, J.

(2000):
In Critical Condition: Polemical Essays on Cognitive Science and the Philosophy of Mind.
MIT Press.

@

Fodor, J.

(2001):
Language, thought and compositionality.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 16, pp. 1-15.

@

Fodor, J.

(2003):
Hume Variations.
Oxford University Press.

@

Fodor, J.

(2004):
Having concepts: A brief refutation of the twentieth Century. Mind and Language 19:29-47. Franks, B. 1992. Realism and folk psychology in the ascription of concepts .
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 5, pp. 369-90.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1968):
Materialism.
In: ' Psychological Explanation '.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1968):
Psychological Explanation.
Random House.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1968):
The appeal to tacit knowledge in psychological explanation.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 65, pp. 627-40.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1974):
Special sciences.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 28, pp. 97-115.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1975):
The Language of Thought.
Harvard University Press.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1975):
Imagistic representation.
In: ' The Language of Thought '.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1978):
Propositional attitudes.
In: ' Monist ', vol. 61, pp. 501-23.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1978):
Tom Swift and his procedural grandmother.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 6, pp. 229-47.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1978):
Computation and reduction.
In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 9.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1980):
Methodological solipsism as a research strategy in cognitive psychology.
In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences ', vol. 3, pp. 63-109.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1980):
Reply to Putnam.
In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.): 'Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky '.
Harvard University Press.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1980):
On the impossibility of acquiring `more powerful' structures.
In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.): 'Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky '.
Harvard University Press.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1981):
Three cheers for propositional attitudes.
In: ' Representations '.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1981):
The present status of the innateness controversy.
In: ' Representations '.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1982):
Cognitive science and the twin-earth problem.
In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic ', vol. 23, pp. 98-118.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1983):
The Modularity of Mind.
MIT Press.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1984):
Semantics, Wisconsin style.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 59, pp. 231-50.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1984):
Observation reconsidered.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 51, pp. 23-43.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1985):
Precis of The modularity of mind.
In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences ', vol. 8, pp. 1-42.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1986):
Information and association.
In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic ', vol. 27.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1986):
Banish DisContent.
In: J. Butterfield (Ed.): 'Language, Mind, and Logic '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1986):
Why paramecia don't have mental representations.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 10, pp. 3-23.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1986):
The modularity of mind.
In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): 'Meaning and Cognitive Structure '.
Ablex.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987):
Why there still has to be a language of thought.
In: ' Psychosemantics '.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987):
Individualism and supervenience.
In: ' Psychosemantics '.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987):
A situated grandmother.
In: ' 1987 '.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987):
Meaning and the world order.
In: ' Psychosemantics '.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987):
Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind.
MIT Press.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987):
Modules, frames, fridgeons, sleeping dogs, and the music of the spheres.
In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): 'The Robot's Dilemma '.
Ablex.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1988):
A reply to Churchland's `Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality'.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 55, pp. 188-98.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1989):
Why should the mind be modular?.
In: A. George (Ed.): 'Reflections on Chomsky '.
Blackwell.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1989):
Making mind matter more.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 17, pp. 59-79.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1990):
A theory of content II.
In: ' A Theory of Content '.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1990):
Information and representation.
In: P. Hanson (Ed.): 'Information, Language and Cognition '.
University of British Columbia Press.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1990):
Psychosemantics, or, Where do truth conditions come from?.
In: W. Lycan (Ed.): 'Mind and Cognition '.
Blackwell.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1990):
A theory of content I.
In: ' A Theory of Content '.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1990):
A Theory of Content and Other Essays.
MIT Press.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1991):
A modal argument for narrow content.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 88, pp. 5-26.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1991):
Yin and Yang in the Chinese Room.
In: D. Rosenthal (Ed.): 'The Nature of Mind '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1991):
You can fool some of the people all of the time, everything else being equal: Hedged laws and psychological explanation .
In: ' Mind ', vol. 100, pp. 19-34.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1994):
The Elm and the Expert.
MIT Press.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(1997):
Connectionism and the problem of systematicity (continued): Why Smolensky's solution still doesn't work .
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 62, pp. 109-19.

@

Fodor, J. A.

(2001):
Doing without What's Within: Fiona Cowie's critique of nativism.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 110, pp. 99-148.

@

Fodor, J. A.; Bever, T.; Garrett, M.

(1974):
The specificity of language skills.
In: ' The Psychology of Language '.

@

Fodor, J. A.; LePore, E.

(1991):
Why meaning (probably) isn't conceptual role.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 6, pp. 328-43.

@

Fodor, J. A.; LePore, E.

(1992):
Holism: A Shopper's Guide.
Blackwell.

@

Fodor, J. A.; LePore, E.

(1993):
Is intentional ascription intrinsically normative?.
In: B. Dahlbom (Ed.): 'Dennett and His Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Fodor, J. A.; LePore, E.

(1993):
Precis of Holism: A Shopper's Guide.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 53, pp. 637-682.

@

Fodor, J. A.; McLaughlin, B. P.

(1990):
Connectionism and the problem of systematicity: Why Smolensky's solution doesn't work.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 35, pp. 183-205.

@

Fodor, J. A.; Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1981):
How direct is visual perception?: Some reflections on Gibson's `ecological approach'.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 9, pp. 139-96.

@

Fodor, J. A.; Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1988):
Connectionism and cognitive architecture.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 28, pp. 3-71.

@

Fodor, J.; Lepore, E.

(1996):
The red herring and the pet fish: Why concepts still can't be prototypes.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 58, pp. 253-70.

@

Fodor, J.; Lepore, E.

(2002):
The Compositionality Papers.
Oxford University Press.

@

Foley, R.

(1978):
Compatibilism.
In: ' Kind ', vol. 87, pp. 421-28.

@

Foley, R.

(1987):
Dretske's `information-theoretic' account of knowledge.
In: ' 1987 '.

@

Fonseca, J.

(2004):
On Bickle's failure to give a formal account of the location in the new-wave reductionist spectrum .
In: ' Disputatio ', vol. 17.

@

Foot, P.

(1957):
Free will as involving determinism.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 66, pp. 439-50.

@

Forbes, G.

(1983):
Scepticism and semantic knowledge.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 84, pp. 223-37.

@

Forbes, G.

(1987):
A dichotomy sustained.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 51, pp. 187-211.

@

Forrest, P.

(1985):
Backwards causation in defense of free will.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 94, pp. 210-17.

@

Forrest, P.

(1988):
Supervenience: The grand-property hypothesis.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 66, pp. 1-12.

@

Forrest, P.

(1992):
Universals and universalisability: An interpretation of Oddie's discussion of supervenience.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 70, pp. 93-98.

@

Forster, M.; Saidel, E.

(1994):
Connectionism and the fate of folk psychology.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 7, pp. 437-52.

@

Forster, M.; Shapiro, L.

(2000):
Prediction and accommodation in evolutionary psychology.
In: ' Psychological Inquiry ', vol. 11, pp. 31-33.

@

Foss, J.

(1994):
On the evolution of intentionality as seen from the intentional stance.
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 37, pp. 287-310.

@

Foss, J.

(1995):
Materialism, reduction, replacement, and the place of consciousness in science.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 92, pp. 401-29.

@

Foss, J. E.

(1985):
A materialist's misgivings about eliminative materialism.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplement ', vol. 11, pp. 105-33.

@

Foss, J. E.

(1992):
Introduction to the epistemology of the brain: Indeterminacy, micro-specificity, chaos, and openness .
In: ' Topoi ', vol. 11, pp. 45-57.

@

Foster, C.

(1990):
Algorithms, abstraction and implementation.
Academic Press.

@

Foster, D.

(2003):
Does colour constancy exist?.
In: ' Trends in Cognitive Science ', vol. 7, pp. 439-443.

@

Foster, J.

(1994):
The token-identity thesis.
In: R. Warner; T. Szubka (Ed.): 'The Mind-Body Problem: A Guide to the Current Debate '.
Blackwell.

@

Foti, V. M.

(1990):
The dimension of color.
In: ' International Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 22, pp. 13-28.

@

Fowler, C.

(1996):
A pragmatic defense of free will.
In: ' Journal of Value Inquiry ', vol. 30, pp. 247-60.

@

Fraassen, van, B.

(2004):
Transcendence of the ego (the nonexistent knight).
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 17, pp. 453-77.

@

Francescotti, R.

(2000):
Ontological physicalism and property pluralism: Why they are incompatible.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 81, pp. 349-362.

@

Francescotti, R.

(2002):
Understanding physical realization (and what it does not entail).
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 23, pp. 279-292.

@

Francescotti, R. M.

(1991):
Externalism and the Marr theory of vision.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 42, pp. 227-38.

@

Francescotti, R. M.

(1997):
What multiple realizability does not show.
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 18, pp. 13-28.

@

Francescotti, R. M.

(1998):
Defining "physicalism".
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 19, pp. 51-64.

@

Francescotti, R. M.

(1998):
The nonreductionist's troubles with supervenience.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 89, pp. 105-24.

@

Frank, M. C.

(2004):
Against informational atomism.
In: ' The Dualist ', vol. 10.

@

Frank, R.

(1988):
Passions Within Reason: The Strategic Role of Emotions.
Norton.

@

Frankfurt, H.

(1969):
Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 65, pp. 829-39.

@

Frankfurt, H.

(1971):
Freedom of the will and the concept of a person.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 68, pp. 5-20.

@

Frankish, K.

(1998):
A matter of opinion.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 11, pp. 423-442.

@

Franklin, S.

(2003):
A conscious artifact?.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 10.

@

Franks, B.

(1995):
On explanation in cognitive science: Competence, idealization, and the failure of the classical cascade .
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 46, pp. 475-502.

@

Franks, B.

(2005):
The role of "the environment" in cognitive and evolutionary psychology.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 18, pp. 59-82.

@

Frapolli, M.; Romero, E.

(2003):
Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind: Essays on Tyler Burge.
CSLI.

@

Frapolli, M.; Romero, E.

(2003):
Anti-individualism and basic self-knowledge.
In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind '.
CSLI.

@

Freeman, N. H.

(1995):
Theories of mind in collision: Plausibility and authority.
In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation '.
Blackwell.

@

Freeman, W.

(1997):
Nonlinear neurodynamics of intentionality.
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 18, pp. 291-304.

@

Freeman, W.; Skarda, C. A.

(1990):
Representations: who needs them?.
In: J. McGaugh; J. Weinberger; G. Lynch (Ed.): 'Brain Organization and Memory '.
Guilford Press.

@

French, R. M.

(1990):
Subcognition and the limits of the Turing test.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 99, pp. 53-66.

@

French, R. M.

(1995):
Refocusing the debate on the Turing Test: A response.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 23, pp. 59-60.

@

Fricker, E.

(1998):
Self-knowledge: Special access vs. artefact of grammar -- A dichotomy rejected.
In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Frijda, N.

(2002):
Emotions and motivational states.
In: ' European Review of Philosophy ', vol. 5, pp. 11-32.

@

Frijda, N. H.

(1986):
The Emotions.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Fuery, P.

(1995):
Theories of Desire.
Melbourne University Press.

@

Fulford, K. W. M.

(1994):
Value, illness, and failure of action: Framework for a philosophical psychopathology of delusions.
In: G. Graham; L. Stephens (Ed.): 'Philosophical Psychopathology '.
MIT Press.

@

Fulford, K. W. M.

(1995):
Mind and madness: New directions in the philosophy of psychiatry.
In: A. Griffiths (Ed.): 'Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychiatry '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Fuller, G.

(1995):
Simulation and psychological concepts.
In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation '.
Blackwell.

@

Fumerton, R.

(2003):
Introspection and internalism.
In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge '.
MIT Press.

@

Funkhouser, E.

(2003):
Willing belief and the norm of truth.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 115, pp. 179-95.

@

Furlong, E. J.

(1948):
Memory.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 57, pp. 16-44.

@

Furlong, E. J.

(1951):
A Study in Memory: A Philosophical Essay.
Nelson.

@

Furlong, E. J.

(1956):
The empiricist theory of memory.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 65, pp. 542-47.

@

Furlong, F. W.

(1981):
Determinism and free will: Review of the literature.
In: ' American Journal of Psychiatry ', vol. 138, pp. 435-39.

@

Gaifman, H.

(2000):
What Godel's incompleteness result does and does not show.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 97, pp. 462-471.

@

Gaita, R.

(1992):
Animal thoughts.
In: ' Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 15, pp. 227-44.

@

Gaito, J.

(1960):
Description, explanation, and reductionism in psychology.
In: ' Psychological Reports ', vol. 6, pp. 203-5.

@

Gaito, J.; Leonard, D.

(1965):
Philosophical and empirical reductionism in psychology.
In: ' Journal of General Psychology ', vol. 72, pp. 69-75.

@

Gallagher, K.

(1964):
Intersubjective knowledge.
In: ' 1964 '.

@

Gallagher, S.

(2001):
The practice of mind: Theory, simulation or primary interaction?.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 8, pp. 83-108.

@

Gallese, V.

(2001):
The 'shared manifold' hypothesis: From mirror neurons to empathy.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 8, pp. 33-50.

@

Gallois, A.

(1977):
Van Inwagen on free will and determinism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 32, pp. 99-105.

@

Gallois, A.

(1994):
Deflationary self-knowledge.
In: M. Michael; J. O'Leary-Hawthorne (Ed.): 'Philosophy in Mind: The Place of Philosophy in the Study of Mind '.
Kluwer.

@

Gallois, A.

(1996):
The World Without, the Mind Within: An Essay on First-Person Authority.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Gallois, A.; O'Leary-Hawthorne, J.

(1996):
Externalism and skepticism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 81, pp. 1-26.

@

Gampel, E. H.

(1997):
The normativity of meaning.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 86, pp. 221-42.

@

Ganeri, J.

(2000):
Cross-modality and the self.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 61, pp. 639-658.

@

Ganeri, J.

(2004):
An irrealist theory of self.
In: ' Harvard Review of Philosophy ', vol. 12.

@

Garcia-Carpintero, M.

(1994):
The supervenience of mental content.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 68, pp. 117-135.

@

Garcia-Carpintero, M.

(1994):
Dretske on the causal efficacy of meaning.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 9, pp. 181-202.

@

Garcia-Carpintero, M.

(1996):
Two spurious varieties of compositionality.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 6, pp. 159-72.

@

Gardenfors, P.

(1997):
Meanings as conceptual structures.
In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind '.
Pittsburgh University Press.

@

Gardner, S.

(1994):
Other minds and embodiment.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 94, pp. 35-52.

@

Gardner, S.

(1996):
Irrationality and the Philosophy of Psychoanalysis.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Garfield, J.

(1987):
Modularity in Knowledge Representation and Natural-Language Understanding.
MIT Press.

@

Garfield, J.

(1988):
Belief in Psychology: A Study in the Ontology of Mind.
MIT Press.

@

Garfield, J.

(1997):
Mentalese not spoken here: Computation, cognition, and causation.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 10, pp. 413-35.

@

Garfield, J.

(2000):
Thought as language: A metaphor too far.
In: ' Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp. 85-101.

@

Garfield, J. L.

(2000):
The meanings of "meaning" and "meaning": Dimensions of the sciences of mind.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 31, pp. 421-440.

@

Garfield, J. L.

(2001):
Pain deproblematized.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 14, pp. 103-7.

@

Garnett, A. C.

(1942):
Scientific method and the concept of emergence.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 39, pp. 477-86.

@

Garnett, A. C.

(1965):
Body and mind: the identity thesis.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 43, pp. 77-81.

@

Garrett B.

(1990):
Personal identity and extrinsicness.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 59, pp. 177-194.

@

Garrett, B.

(1991):
Personal identity and reductionism.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 51, pp. 361-373.

@

Garrett, B.

(1992):
Persons and values.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 42, pp. 337-44.

@

Garrett, B. J.

(1998):
Pluralism, causation, and overdetermination.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 116, pp. 355-78.

@

Garrett, B. J.

(1999):
Davidson on causal relevance.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 12, pp. 14-33.

@

Garson, J.

(2003):
Simulation and connectionism: What is the connection?.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 16, pp. 499-515.

@

Garson, J.

(2003):
The introduction of information into neurobiology.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 70, pp. 926-936.

@

Garson, J. W.

(1991):
What connectionists cannot do: The threat to Classical AI.
In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind '.
Kluwer.

@

Garson, J. W.

(1993):
Mice in mirrored mazes and the mind.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 6, pp. 123-34.

@

Garson, J. W.

(1994):
No representations without rules: The prospects for a compromise between paradigms in cognitive science .
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 9, pp. 25-37.

@

Garson, J. W.

(1994):
Cognition without classical architecture.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 100, pp. 291-306.

@

Garson, J. W.

(1995):
Chaos and free will.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 8, pp. 365-74.

@

Garson, J. W.

(1995):
Chaos and free will.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 8, pp. 365-74.

@

Garson, J. W.

(1996):
Cognition poised at the edge of chaos: A complex alternative to a symbolic mind.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 9, pp. 301-22.

@

Garson, J. W.

(1997):
Syntax in a dynamic brain.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 110, pp. 343-55.

@

Garson, J. W.

(1997):
Syntax in a dynamic brain.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 110, pp. 343-355.

@

Garson, J. W.

(1998):
Chaotic emergence and the language of thought.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 11, pp. 303-315.

@

Garzon, F.

(2000):
A connectionist defence of the inscrutability thesis.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 15, pp. 465-480.

@

Garzon, F.

(2000):
State space semantics and conceptual similarity: reply to Churchland.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 13, pp. 77-96.

@

Garzon, F. C.

(2001):
Can we turn a blind eye to eliminativism?.
In: ' International Journal of Philosophical Studies ', vol. 9, pp. 485-498.

@

Gates, G.

(2001):
Physicalism, empiricism, and positivism.
In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Gauker, C.

(1987):
Mind and chance.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 17, pp. 533-52.

@

Gauker, C.

(1988):
Objective interpretationism.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 69, pp. 136-51.

@

Gauker, C.

(1990):
How to learn language like a chimpanzee.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 4, pp. 139-46.

@

Gauker, C.

(1991):
Mental content and the division of epistemic labour.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 69, pp. 302-18.

@

Gauker, C.

(1993):
Holism without meaning: A critical review of Fodor and Lepore's Holism: A Shopper's Guide.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 6, pp. 441-49.

@

Gauker, C.

(1993):
An extraterrestrial perspective on conceptual development.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 8, pp. 105-30.

@

Gauker, C.

(1995):
Thinking Out Loud: An Essay on the Relation between Thought and Language.
Princeton University Press.

@

Gauker, C.

(1995):
A new skeptical solution.
In: ' Acta Analytica: ', vol. 113.

@

Gauker, C.

(2003):
Attitudes without psychology.
In: ' Facta Philosophica ', vol. 5, pp. 239-56.

@

Gauker, C.

(2003):
Social externalism and linguistic communication.
In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind '.
CSLI.

@

Geach, P.

(1957):
Mental Acts.
Routledge and Kegan Paul.

@

Gelder, van, T.

(1990):
Compositionality: A connectionist variation on a classical theme.
In: ' Cognitive Science ', vol. 14, pp. 355-84.

@

Gelder, van, T.

(1991):
Classical questions, radical answers.
In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind '.
Kluwer.

@

Gelder, van, T.

(1991):
What is the D in PDP?.
In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Gelder, van, T.

(1993):
The distinction between mind and cognition.
In: Y. Houng; J. Ho (Ed.): 'Mind and Cognition: 1993 International Symposium '.
Academia Sinica.

@

Gelder, van, T.

(1995):
What might cognition be if not computation?.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 92, pp. 345-81.

@

Gelder, van, T.

(1995):
What might cognition be if not computation?.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 92, pp. 345-81.

@

Gelder, van, T.

(1997):
Connectionism, dynamics, and the philosophy of mind.
In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind '.
Pittsburgh University Press.

@

Gelder, van, T.

(1998):
Monism, dualism, pluralism.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp. 76-97.

@

Gelder, van, T.

(1998):
The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science.
In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences ', vol. 21, pp. 615-28.

@

Gelder, van, T.

(1998):
The roles of philosophy in cognitive science.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 11, pp. 117-36.

@

Gelder, van, T.; Port, R.

(1995):
Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition.
MIT Press.

@

Gendler, T.

(2002):
Personal identity and thought-experiments.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 52, pp. 34-54.

@

Gendron, B.

(1970):
On the relation of neurological and psychological theories: A critique of the hardware thesis.
In: ' Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 8, pp. 483-95.

@

Gennaro, R. J.

(1992):
Consciousness, self-consciousness, and episodic memory.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 5, pp. 333-47.

@

Georgalis, N.

(1990):
No access for the externalist: Discussion of Heil's "Privileged access".
In: ' Mind ', vol. 100, pp. 101-8.

@

Georgalis, N.

(1994):
Asymmetry of access to intentional states.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 40, pp. 185-211.

@

Georgalis, N.

(1999):
Rethinking Burge's thought experiment.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 118, pp. 145-64.

@

George, A.; Velleman, D. J.

(2000):
Leveling the playing field between mind and machine: A reply to McCall.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 97, pp. 456-452.

@

George, F.

(1962):
Minds, machines and Godel: Another reply to Mr. Lucas.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 37, pp. 62-63.

@

Gerrans, P.

(2002):
The theory of mind module in evolutionary psychology.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 17, pp. 305-21.

@

Gerrans, P.

(2002):
A one-stage explanation of the Cotard delusion.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology ', vol. 9, pp. 47-53.

@

Gerrans, P.

(2003):
Nativism and neuroconstructivism in the explanation of Williams syndrome.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 18, pp. 41-52.

@

Gerrans, P.

(2004):
Cognitive architecture and the limits of interpretationism.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology ', vol. 11, pp. 42-48.

@

Gertler, B.

(2000):
The mechanics of self-knowledge.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 28, pp. 125-46.

@

Gertler, B.

(2000):
Functionalism's methodological predicament.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 38, pp. 77-94.

@

Gertler, B.

(2003):
Self-knowledge.
In: ' 2003 '.

@

Gertler, B.

(2003):
Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self-Knowledge.
Ashgate.

@

Gertler, B.

(2004):
We can't know a priori that H2O exists. But can we know a priori that water does?.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 64, pp. 44-47.

@

Gianfranco, S.

(2002):
Reply to 'From simulation to theory'.
In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action '.
John Benjamins.

@

Gibb, S. C.

(2004):
The problem of mental causation and the nature of properties.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 82, pp. 464-75.

@

Gibbard, A.

(1996):
Thoughts, norms, and discursive practices: Commentary on Brandom.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 56, pp. 699-717.

@

Gibbard, A.

(2002):
Normative explanations: Invoking rationality to explain happenings.
In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature '.
Clarendon.

@

Gibbard, A.

(2003):
Thoughts and norms.
In: ' Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp. 83-98.

@

Gibbons, J.

(1993):
Identity without supervenience.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 70, pp. 59-79.

@

Gibbons, J.

(1996):
Externalism and knowledge of content.
In: ' Philsophical Review ', vol. 105, pp. 287-310.

@

Gibbons, J.

(2001):
Externalism and knowledge of the attitudes.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 51, pp. 13-28.

@

Gibson, J. J.

(1979):
The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.
Houghton Mifflin.

@

Gibson, M.

(1996):
Asymmetric dependencies, ideal conditions, and meaning.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 9, pp. 235-59.

@

Gilbert, M.

(2002):
Belief and acceptance as features of groups.
In: ' Protosociology ', vol. 16, pp. 35-69.

@

Gilbert, P.

(1987):
Westphal and Wittgenstein on white.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 76, pp. 399-403.

@

Gilbert, P.

(1989):
Reflections on white: A rejoinder to Westphal.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 98, pp. 423-6.

@

Gill, J. H.

(1980):
Of split brains and tacit knowing.
In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 20, pp. 49-58.

@

Gillett, C.

(2001):
The methodological role of physicalism: A minimal skepticism.
In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Gillett, C.

(2003):
The metaphysics of realization, multiple realizability, and the special sciences.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 100, pp. 591-603.

@

Gillett, C.

(2003):
Nonreductive realization and nonreductive identity: What physicalism does not entail.
In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation '.
Imprint Academic.

@

Gillett, C.; Loewer, B.

(2001):
Physicalism and its Discontents.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Gillett, C.; Rives, B.

(2001):
Does the argument from realization generalize? Responses to Kim.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 39, pp. 79-98.

@

Gillett, G.

(1986):
Brain bisection and personal identity.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 95, pp. 224-9.

@

Gillett, G.

(1986):
Multiple personality and the concept of a person.
In: ' New Ideas in Psychology ', vol. 4, pp. 173-84.

@

Gillett, G.

(1987):
Reasoning about persons.
In: A. Peacocke; G. Gillett (Ed.): 'Persons and Personality: A Contemporary Inquiry '.
Blackwell.

@

Gillett, G.

(1989):
Representations and cognitive science.
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 32, pp. 261-77.

@

Gillett, G.

(1991):
The neurophilosophy of pain.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 66, pp. 191-206.

@

Gillett, G.

(1992):
Representation, Meaning, and Thought.
Oxford University Press.

@

Gillett, G.

(1995):
Humpty Dumpty and the night of the triffids: Individualism and rule-following.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 105, pp. 191-206.

@

Gillett, G.

(1997):
A discursive account of multiple personality disorder.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology ', vol. 4, pp. 213-22.

@

Gillett, G.

(2001):
Free will and events in the brain.
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 22, pp. 287-310.

@

Gilman, D.

(1993):
Optimization and simplicity: Marr's theory of vision and biological explanation.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 107, pp. 293-323.

@

Ginet, C.

(1980):
The conditional analysis of freedom.
In: P. van Inwagen (Ed.): 'Time and Cause: Essays Presented to Richard Taylor '.
Reidel.

@

Ginet, C.

(1983):
In defense of incompatibilism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 44, pp. 391-400.

@

Ginet, C.

(1989):
Reasons explanation of action: An incompatibilist account.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 3.

@

Ginet, C.

(1990):
On Action.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Ginet, C.

(1992):
The dispositionalist solutions to Wittgenstein's problem about understanding a rule: Answering Kripke's objection .
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 17.

@

Ginet, C.

(1996):
In defense of the principle of alternative possibilities: Why I don't find Frankfurt's argument convincing .
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 10, pp. 403-17.

@

Ginet, C.

(2002):
Reasons and explanations of action: Causalist versus noncausalist accounts.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Gips, J.

(1994):
Toward the ethical robot.
In: K. M. Ford; C. Glymour; P. Hayes (Ed.): 'Android Epistemology '.
MIT Press.

@

Giunti, M.

(1995):
Dynamic models of cognition.
In: T. van Gelder; R. Port (Ed.): 'Mind as Motion '.
MIT Press.

@

Giunti, M.

(1996):
Computers, Dynamical Systems, and the Mind.
Oxford University Press.

@

Gjelsvik, O.

(1991):
Dretske on knowledge and content.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 86, pp. 425-41.

@

Glasgow, J. I.

(1993):
The imagery debate revisited: A computational perspective.
In: ' Computational Intelligence ', vol. 9, pp. 310-33.

@

Glasgow, W. D.; Pilkington, G. W.

(1970):
Other minds on evidential necessity.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 79, pp. 431-35.

@

Glennan, S. S.

(1995):
Computationalism and the problem of other minds.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 8, pp. 375-88.

@

Glennan, S. S.

(1995):
Computationalism and the problem of other minds.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 8, pp. 375-88.

@

Globus, G.

(1984):
Can methodological solipsism be confined to psychology?.
In: ' Cognition and Brain Theory ', vol. 7, pp. 233-46.

@

Globus, G.

(1989):
The strict identity theory of Schlick, Russell, Maxwell, and Feigl.
In: M. Maxwell; C. Savage (Ed.): 'Science, Mind, and Psychology: Essays in Honor of Grover Maxwell '.
University Press of America.

@

Globus, G.

(1991):
Deconstructing the Chinese room.
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 12, pp. 377-91.

@

Globus, G.

(1992):
Toward a noncomputational cognitive science.
In: ' Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience ', vol. 4, pp. 299-310.

@

Globus, G. G.

(1992):
Derrida and connectionism: Differance in neural nets.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 5, pp. 183-97.

@

Glock, H.

(2000):
Animals, thoughts and concepts.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 123, pp. 35-104.

@

Glock, H. J.; Preston, J. M.

(1995):
Externalism and first-person authority.
In: ' Monist ', vol. 78, pp. 515-33.

@

Glover, J.

(1988):
I: The Philosophy and Psychology of Personal Identity.
Penguin.

@

Gluer, K.

(1999):
Sense and prescriptivity.
In: ' Acta Analytica ', vol. 14.

@

Glymour, C.

(1988):
AI is philosophy.
In: J. Fetzer (Ed.): 'Aspects of AI '.
D.

@

Glymour, C.

(1994):
On the methods of cognitive neuropsychology.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 45, pp. 815-35.

@

Glymour, C.

(2000):
Android epistemology for babies.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 122, pp. 53-68.

@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(1986):
Why semantic properties won't earn their keep.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 50, pp. 223-36.

@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(1989):
Misinformation.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 19, pp. 533-50.

@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(1991):
Signal, decision, action.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 88, pp. 709-22.

@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(1996):
Complexity and the Function of Mind in Nature.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(2002):
On the evolution of representational and interpretive capacities.
In: ' Monist ', vol. 85, pp. 50-69.

@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(2002):
Environmental complexity and the evolution of cognition.
In: R. Sternberg and J. Kaufman (Ed.): 'The Evolution of Intelligence '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(2004):
On folk psychology and mental representation.
In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Representation in Mind '.
Elsevier.

@

Godow, R.

(1976):
Eliminative materialism and denotation.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 36.

@

Goel, V.

(1991):
Notationality and the information processing mind.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp. 129-166.

@

Goguen, J.

(2004):
Musical qualia, context, time and emotion.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 11.

@

Gold, I.

(1999):
On Lewis on naming the colours.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 77, pp. 365-370.

@

Gold, I.

(1999):
Dispositions and the central problem of color.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 93, pp. 21-44.

@

Gold, I.; Hohwy, J.

(2000):
Rationality and schizophrenic delusion.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 15, pp. 146-167.

@

Goldberg, B.

(1977):
A problem with anomalous monism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 32, pp. 175-80.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(1997):
Self-ascription, self-knowledge, and the memory argument.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 57, pp. 211-19.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(1999):
The relevance of discriminatory knowledge of content.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 80, pp. 136-56.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(1999):
The psychology and epistemology of self-knowledge.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 118, pp. 165-201.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2000):
Externalism and authoritative knowledge of content: A new incompatibilist strategy.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 100, pp. 51-79.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2002):
Belief and its linguistic expression: Toward a belief box account of first-person authority.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 1, pp. 65-76.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2002):
Do anti-individualistic construals of propositional attitudes capture the agent's conception?.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 36, pp. 597-621.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2003):
On our alleged a priori knowledge that water exists.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 63, pp. 38-41.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2003):
Anti-individualism, conceptual omniscience, and skepticism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 116, pp. 53-78.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2003):
What do you know when you know your own thoughts?.
In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge '.
MIT Press.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2005):
(Nonstandard) lessons from world-switching cases.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 32, pp. 85-131.

@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2005):
The dialectical context of Boghossian's memory argument.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 35, pp. 135-48.

@

Goldfarb, W.

(1982):
Kripke on Wittgenstein on rules.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 82, pp. 471-488.

@

Goldie, P.

(2000):
The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration.
Oxford University Press.

@

Goldie, P.

(2004):
Emotion, reason, and virtue.
In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): 'Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Goldie, P.

(2004):
Emotion, feeling, and knowledge of the world.
In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Goldman, A.

(1968):
Actions, predictions, and books of life.
In: ' 1968 '.

@

Goldman, A.

(1969):
The compatibility of mechanism and purpose.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 78, pp. 468-82.

@

Goldman, A.

(1986):
Constraints on representation.
In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): 'The Representation of Knowledge and Belief '.
University of Arizona Press.

@

Goldman, A.

(1989):
Interpretation psychologized.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 4, pp. 161-85.

@

Goldman, A.

(1992):
The psychology of folk psychology.
In: ' 1992 '.

@

Goldman, A.

(1992):
In defense of the simulation theory.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 7, pp. 104-119.

@

Goldman, A.

(1996):
Simulation and interpersonal utility.
In: L. May; M. Friedman; A. Clark (Ed.): 'Mind and Morals: Essays on Ethics and Cognitive Science '.
MIT Press.

@

Goldman, A.

(2000):
Folk psychology and mental concepts.
In: ' Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp. 4-25.

@

Goldman, A.

(2002):
Simulation theory and mental concepts.
In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action '.
John Benjamins.

@

Goldman, A.

(2002):
The mentalizing folk.
In: ' Protosociology ', vol. 16, pp. 7-34.

@

Goldman, A.

(2006):
Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading.
Oxford University Press.

@

Goldstein, I.

(1980):
Why people prefer pleasure to pain.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 55.

@

Goldstein, I.

(1989):
Pleasure and pain: unconditional intrinsic values.
In: ' 1989 '.

@

Goldstein, I.

(1994):
Identifying mental states: A celebrated hypothesis refuted.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 72, pp. 46-62.

@

Goldstein, I.

(1999):
Intersubjective properties by which we specify pain, pleasure, and other kinds of mental states.
In: ' 1999 '.

@

Gomberg, P.

(1975):
Free will as ultimate responsibility.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 15, pp. 205-12.

@

Good, I. J.

(1967):
Human and machine logic.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 18, pp. 145-6.

@

Good, I. J.

(1969):
Godel's theorem is a red herring.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 19, pp. 357-8.

@

Goodenough, J. M.

(1996):
Parfit and the Sorites paradox.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 2, pp. 113-20.

@

Goodman, R.

(1985):
Cavell and the problem of other minds.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 13, pp. 43-52.

@

Goodman, R. B.

(1974):
A note on eliminative materialism.
In: ' Journal of Critical Analysis ', vol. 5, pp. 80-83.

@

Gopnik, A.

(1990):
Developing the idea of intentionality: Children's theories of mind.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 20, pp. 89-114.

@

Gopnik, A.

(1997):
The scientist as child.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 63, pp. 485-514.

@

Gopnik, A.

(2003):
The theory theory as an alternative to the innateness hypothesis.
In: L. Antony (Ed.): 'Chomsky and His Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Gopnik, A. and Meltzoff, AN.

(1998):
Theories vs. modules: To the max and beyond. A reply to Poulin-Dubois and to Stich and Nichols.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp. 450-456.

@

Gopnik, A.; Wellman, H.

(1992):
Why the child's theory of mind really is a theory.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 7, pp. 145-71.

@

Gopnik, A.; Wellman, H. M.

(1995):
Why the child's theory of mind really is a theory.
In: ' 1995 '.

@

Gordon, R. M.

(1974):
The aboutness of emotions.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 27, pp. 11-36.

@

Gordon, R. M.

(1986):
Folk psychology as simulation.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 1, pp. 158-71.

@

Gordon, R. M.

(1986):
The passivity of emotions.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 95, pp. 339-60.

@

Gordon, R. M.

(1987):
The Structure of Emotions: Investigations in Cognitive Philosophy.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Gordon, R. M.

(1992):
The simulation theory: objections and misconceptions.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 7, pp. 11-34.

@

Gordon, R. M.

(1995):
Simulation without introspection or inference from me to you.
In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation '.
Blackwell.

@

Gordon, R. M.

(1996):
Sympathy, simulation, and the impartial spectator.
In: L. May; M. Friedman; A. Clark (Ed.): 'Mind and Morals: Essays on Ethics and Cognitive Science '.
MIT Press.

@

Gordon, R. M.

(1996):
`Radical' simulationism.
In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Gordon, R. M.

(2000):
Sellars's Rylean ancestors revisited.
In: ' Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp. 102-114.

@

Gordon, R. M.; Barker, J. A.

(1994):
Autism and the "theory of mind" debate.
In: G. Graham; G. L. Stephens (Ed.): 'Philosophical Psychopathology '.
MIT Press.

@

Goschke, T.; Koppelberg, D.

(1990):
Connectionism and the semantic content of internal representation.
In: ' Review of International Philosophy ', vol. 44, pp. 87-103.

@

Goschke, T.; Koppelberg, D.

(1991):
The concept of representation and the representation of concepts in connectionist models.
In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Gosselin, P.

(1987):
The principle of alternative possibilities.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 17, pp. 91-104.

@

Gottlieb, D. F.

(1983):
Wittgenstein's critique of the "Tractatus" view of rules.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 56, pp. 239-251.

@

Goudge, T. A.

(1982):
Ryle's last thoughts on thinking.
In: ' Dialogue ', vol. 21, pp. 125-32.

@

Gould, J. L.; Gould, C. G.

(1982):
The insect mind: Physics or metaphysics?.
In: D. Griffin (Ed.): 'Animal Mind -- Human Mind '.
Springer-Verlag.

@

Gould, J. L.; Gould, C. G.

(1994):
The Animal Mind.
Scientific American Library.

@

Gozzano, S.

(1995):
Consciousness and understanding in the Chinese room.
In: ' Informatica ', vol. 19, pp. 653-56.

@

Graham, G,; Stephens, L.

(1994):
Philosophical Psychopathology.
MIT Press.

@

Graham, G.

(1982):
Spartans and behaviorists.
In: ' Behaviorism ', vol. 10.

@

Graham, G.

(1987):
The origins of folk psychology.
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 30, pp. 357-79.

@

Graham, G.

(1993):
Philosophy of Mind: An Introduction.
Blackwell.

@

Graham, G.; Horgan, T.

(1988):
How to be realistic about folk psychology.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 1.

@

Graham, G.; Horgan, T.

(1992):
Southern fundamentalism and the end of philosophy.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Truth and Rationality '.
Ridgeview.

@

Graham, G.; Stephens, G.

(1987):
Minding your P's and Q's: Pain and sensible qualities.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 21, pp. 395-405.

@

Graham, G.; Stephens, L.

(1994):
An introduction to philosophical psychopathology: Its nature, scope, and emergence.
In: G. Graham; L. Stephens (Ed.): 'Philosophical Psychopathology '.
MIT Press.

@

Grahek, N.

(1991):
Objective and subjective aspects of pain.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 4, pp. 249-66.

@

Grahek, N.

(1995):
The sensory dimension of pain.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 79, pp. 167-84.

@

Grandy, R.

(1987):
Information-based epistemology, ecological epistemology and epistemology naturalized.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 70, pp. 191-203.

@

Grandy, R. E.

(1989):
Concepts, prototypes, and information.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Information, Semantics, and Epistemology '.
Blackwell.

@

Grantham, T. A.; Nichols, S.

(1999):
Evolutionary psychology: Ultimate explanations and Panglossian predictions.
In: V. Hardcastle (Ed.): 'Where Biology Meets Psychology '.
MIT Press.

@

Gray, R.

(2001):
Cognitive modules, synaesthesia and the constitution of psychological natural kinds.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 14, pp. 65-82.

@

Green, O.

(1992):
The Emotions: A Philosophical Theory.
Kluwer.

@

Greene, R.

(2003):
Constitutive theories of self-knowledge and the regress problem.
In: ' Philosophical Papers ', vol. 32, pp. 141-48.

@

Greenspan, P. S.

(1978):
Behavior control and freedom of action.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 87, pp. 225-40.

@

Greenspan, P. S.

(1988):
Emotions and Reasons: An Enquiry into Emotional Justification.
Routledge.

@

Greenspan, P. S.

(1993):
Free will and the genome project.
In: ' Philosophy and Public Affairs ', vol. 22, pp. 31-43.

@

Greenspan, P. S.

(2004):
Emotions, rationality, and mind-body.
In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1991):
Reasons to believe.
In: J. Greenwood (Ed.): 'The Future of Folk Psychology '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1991):
Self-knowledge: Looking in the wrong direction.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 19, pp. 35-47.

@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1991):
The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1992):
Against eliminative materialism: from folk psychology to Volkerpsychologie.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 5, pp. 349-68.

@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1993):
Split brains and singular personhood.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 31, pp. 285-306.

@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1999):
Simulation, theory-theory and cognitive penetration: No "instance of the fingerpost".
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 14, pp. 32-56.

@

Griffin, D. R.

(1982):
Animal Mind -- Human Mind.
Springer-Verlag.

@

Griffin, D. R.

(1984):
Animal Thinking.
Harvard University Press.

@

Griffin, D. R.

(1992):
Animal Minds.
University of Chicago Press.

@

Griffiths, A.

(1995):
Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychiatry.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Griffiths, A. P.

(1989):
Is free will incompatible with something or other?.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 24, pp. 101-19.

@

Griffiths, P. E.

(1989):
Folk, functional and neurochemical aspects of mood.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 2, pp. 17-32.

@

Griffiths, P. E.

(1997):
What Emotions Really Are: The Problem of Psychological Categories.
University of Chicago Press.

@

Griffiths, P. E.

(2002):
Emotions.
In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind '.
Blackwell.

@

Griffiths, P. E.

(2003):
Basic emotions, complex emotions, Machiavellian emotions.
In: A. Hatimoysis (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Emotions '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Griffiths, P. E.

(2004):
Toward a "Machiavellian" theory of emotional appraisal.
In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): 'Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Griffiths, P. E.

(2004):
Is emotion a natural kind?.
In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Grim, P.

(1997):
Worlds by supervenience: Some further problems.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 2, pp. 146-51.

@

Grim, P.; St. Denis, P.; Kokalis, T.

(2004):
Information and meaning: Use-based models in arrays of neural nets.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 14, pp. 43-66.

@

Grimaltos, T.

(2003):
Terms and content.
In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind '.
CSLI.

@

Grimes, T.

(1988):
The myth of supervenience.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 69, pp. 152-60.

@

Grimes, T.

(1991):
Supervenience, determination, and dependency.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 62, pp. 81-92.

@

Grimes, T.

(1995):
The Tweedledum and Tweedledee of supervenience.
In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Grunbaum, A.

(1971):
Free will and the laws of human behavior.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 8, pp. 299-317.

@

Grunbaum, A.

(1972):
Abelson on Feigl's mind-body identity thesis.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 23, pp. 119-21.

@

Grunbaum, A.

(1994):
The placebo concept in medicine and psychiatry.
In: G. Graham; L. Stephens (Ed.): 'Philosophical Psychopathology '.
MIT Press.

@

Grush, R.

(1997):
The architecture of representation.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 10, pp. 5-23.

@

Grush, R.

(2001):
The semantic challenge to computational neuroscience.
In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences '.
University of Pittsburgh Press.

@

Grush, R.

(2003):
In defense of some "Cartesian" assumption concerning the brain and its operation.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 18, pp. 53-92.

@

Grush, R.; Churchland, P.

(1995):
Gaps in Penrose's toiling.
In: T. Metzinger (Ed.): 'Conscious Experience '.
Ferdinand Schoningh.

@

Guarini, M.

(1996):
Tensor products and split-level architecture: Foundational issues in the classicism-connectionism debate .
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 63.

@

Guarini, M.

(2001):
A defence of connectionism against the "syntactic" argument.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 128, pp. 287-317.

@

Gulick, van, R.

(1980):
Functionalism, information and content.
In: ' Nature and System ', vol. 2, pp. 139-62.

@

Gulick, van, R.

(1980):
Rationality and the anomalous nature of the mental.
In: ' Philosophy Research Archives ', vol. 7.

@

Gulick, van, R.

(1982):
Mental representation: A functionalist view.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 63, pp. 3-20.

@

Gulick, van, R.

(1982):
Functionalism as a theory of mind.
In: ' Philosophy Research Archives ', vol. 185.

@

Gulick, van, R.

(1989):
Metaphysical arguments for internalism and why they don't work.
In: S. Silvers (Ed.): 'ReRepresentation '.
Kluwer.

@

Gulick, van, R.

(1992):
Nonreductive materialism and the nature of intertheoretical constraint.
In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism '.
De Gruyter.

@

Gulick, van, R.

(1993):
Who's in charge here? And who's doing all the work?.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Gulick, van, R.

(1994):
Are beliefs brain states? And if they are what might that explain?.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 76, pp. 205-15.

@

Gulick, van, R.

(2000):
Inward and upward: Reflection, introspection, and self-awareness.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 28, pp. 275-305.

@

Gulick, van, R.

(2001):
Reduction, emergence and other recent options on the mind/body problem: A philosophic overview.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 8, pp. 1-34.

@

Gunderson, K.

(1964):
The imitation game.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 73, pp. 234-45.

@

Gunderson, K.

(1968):
Robots, consciousness and programmed behaviour.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 19, pp. 109-22.

@

Gunderson, K.

(1969):
Cybernetics and mind-body problems.
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 12, pp. 406-19.

@

Gunderson, K.

(1971):
Mentality and Machines.
Doubleday.

@

Gunther, Y.

(2003):
Emotion and force.
In: Y. Gunther (Ed.): 'Essays on Nonconceptual Content '.
MIT Press.

@

Gunther, Y.

(2004):
The phenomenology and intentionality of emotion.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 117, pp. 43-55.

@

Gustafson, D.

(1995):
Belief in pain.
In: ' Consciousness and Cognition ', vol. 4, pp. 323-45.

@

Gustafson, D.

(2000):
On the supposed utility of a folk theory of pain.
In: ' Brain and Mind ', vol. 1, pp. 223-228.

@

Gustafson, D. F.

(1963):
On the identity theory.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 24, pp. 30-32.

@

Guttenplan, S.

(1994):
Belief, knowledge, and the origins of content.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 48, pp. 287-305.

@

Guttenplan, S.

(2000):
Mind's Landscape: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind.
Blackwell Publishers.

@

Hacker, P. M. S.

(1972):
Other minds and Professor Ayer's concept of a person.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 32, pp. 341-354.

@

Hacking, I.

(1985):
Rules, scepticism, proof, Wittgenstein. In (I.
In: ' 1985 '.

@

Hacking, I.

(1991):
Two souls in one body.
In: ' Critical Inquiry ', vol. 17, pp. 838-67.

@

Hacking, I.

(1993):
On Kripke's and Goodman's uses of 'grue'.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 68.

@

Hacking, I.

(1995):
Rewriting the Soul: Multiple Personality and the Sciences of Memory.
Princeton University Press.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1987):
Godel, Lucas, and mechanical models of mind.
In: ' Computational Intelligence ', vol. 3, pp. 57-63.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1990):
Truth conditions and procedural semantics.
In: P. Hanson (Ed.): 'Information, Language and Cognition '.
University of British Columbia Press.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1990):
Connectionism, rule-following, and symbolic manipulation.
In: ' 1990 '.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1991):
The many uses of `belief' in AI.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp. 55-74.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1993):
Connectionism, explicit rules, and symbolic manipulation.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 3.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1994):
Systematicity in connectionist language learning.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 9, pp. 247-72.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1994):
Systematicity revisited.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 9, pp. 431-44.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1995):
The `explicit-implicit' distinction.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 5, pp. 219-42.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1997):
Cognition, systematicity, and nomic necessity.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 12, pp. 137-53.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1997):
Cognition, systematicity, and nomic necessity.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 12, pp. 137-53.

@

Hadley, R. F.

(1997):
Explaining systematicity: A reply to Kenneth Aizawa.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 12, pp. 571-79.

@

Hadley, R. F.; Hayward, M. B.

(1997):
Strong semantic systematicity from Hebbian connectionist learning.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 7, pp. 1-55.

@

Hahn, M.

(2003):
When swampmen get arthritis: "Externalism" in Burge and Davidson.
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Hahn, M.; Ramberg, B.

(2003):
Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge.
MIT Press.

@

Haight, D.; Haight, M.

(1989):
Time, memory, and self-remembering.
In: ' Journal of Speculative Philosophy ', vol. 3, pp. 1-11.

@

Hajek, A.; Pettit, P.

(2004):
Desire beyond belief.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 82, pp. 77-92.

@

Haji, I.

(2002):
Compatibilist views of freedom and responsibility.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Haji, I.; Cuypers, S.

(2001):
Libertarian free will and CNC manipulation.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 55, pp. 221-238.

@

Haldane, J.

(1988):
Understanding folk.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 62, pp. 222-46.

@

Haldane, J.

(1996):
The mystery of emergence.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 96, pp. 261-67.

@

Haldane, J.

(2000):
The state and fate of contemporary philosophy of mind.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 37, pp. 301-21.

@

Haldane, J. J.

(1989):
Naturalism and the problem of intentionality.
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 32, pp. 305-22.

@

Haldane, J. J.

(1994):
Analytical philosophy and the nature of mind: Time for another rebirth?.
In: R. Warner; T. Szubka (Ed.): 'The Mind-Body Problem: A Guide to the Current Debate '.
Blackwell.

@

Hale, B.

(1997):
Rule-following, objectivity and meaning.
In: B. Hale; C. Wright (Ed.): 'A Companion to the Philosophy of Language '.
Blackwell.

@

Hall, L.

(1998):
The self-knowledge that externalists leave out.
In: ' Southwest Philosophy Review ', vol. 14.

@

Hall, R. J.

(1989):
Are pains necessarily unpleasant?.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 49, pp. 643-59.

@

Hall, R. J.

(1996):
The evolution of color vision without colors.
In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement ', vol. 63, pp. 125-33.

@

Hamer, C.

(1970):
Why Ryle is not a behaviourist.
In: ' Philosophical Studies (Ireland) ', vol. 17, pp. 7-25.

@

Hamilton, A.

(1995):
A new look at personal identity.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 45, pp. 332-349.

@

Hamlyn, D. W.

(1953):
Behaviour.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 28, pp. 132-45.

@

Hampshire, S.

(1952):
The analogy of feeling.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 61, pp. 1-12.

@

Hanfling, O.

(1984):
What does the private language argument prove?.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 34, pp. 468-481.

@

Hanfling, O.

(1985):
Was Wittgenstein a sceptic?.
In: ' Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 8, pp. 1-16.

@

Hanna, P.

(1985):
Causal powers and cognition.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 94, pp. 53-63.

@

Hannan, B.

(1990):
`Non-scientific realism' about propositional attitudes as a response to eliminativist arguments.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 18, pp. 21-31.

@

Hannan, B.

(1993):
Don't stop believing: the case against eliminative materialism.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 8, pp. 165-179.

@

Hannay, A.

(1971):
Mental Images: A Defense.
Allen & Unwin.

@

Hannay, A.

(1973):
To see a mental image.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 82, pp. 161-262.

@

Hannay, B.

(1994):
Subjectivity and Reduction: An Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem.
Westview Press.

@

Hanratty, G.

(1972):
The identity theory of Herbert Feigl.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 20, pp. 113-23.

@

Hanson, N. R.

(1952):
Professor Ryle's "mind".
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 2, pp. 246-48.

@

Hanson, S.; Burr, D.

(1990):
What connectionist models learn.
In: ' 1990 '.

@

Hanson, W.

(1971):
Mechanism and Godel's theorem.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 22, pp. 9-16.

@

Hardcastle, V.

(1996):
How to Build a Theory in Cognitive Science.
SUNY Press.

@

Hardcastle, V.

(2002):
On the normativity of functions.
In: A. Ariew (Ed.): 'Functions '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Hardcastle, V.

(2003):
Emotions and narrative selves.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology ', vol. 10, pp. 353-356.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1992):
Reduction, explanatory extension, and the mind/brain sciences.
In: ' <i>Philosophy of Science</i> ', vol. 59, pp. 408-28.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1992):
Reduction, explanatory extension, and the mind/brain sciences.
In: ' <i>Philosophy of Science</i> ', vol. 59, pp. 408-28.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1994):
Indicator semantics and Dretske's function.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 7, pp. 367-82.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1995):
Computationalism.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 105, pp. 303-17.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1997):
is explanation better.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 64, pp. 154-60.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1997):
When a pain is not.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 94, pp. 381-409.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1998):
On the matter of minds and mental causation.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 58, pp. 1-25.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1999):
Where Biology Meets Psychology: Philosophical Essays.
MIT Press.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(2000):
The Myth of Pain.
MIT Press.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.; Stewart, C. M.

(2001):
Theory structure in neuroscience.
In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences '.
University of Pittsburgh Press.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.; Stewart, C. M.

(2002):
What do brain data really show?.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 69, pp. 572-582.

@

Hardcastle, V. G.; Stewart, C. M.

(2004):
Neuroscience and the art of single-cell recordings.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 18, pp. 195-208.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1983):
Colors, normal observers and standard conditions.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 80, pp. 806-13.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1984):
A new look at color.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 21, pp. 125-33.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1984):
Are scientific objects colored?.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 93, pp. 491-500.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1985):
The resemblances of colors.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 48, pp. 35-47.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1985):
Frank talk about the colors of sense-data.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 63, pp. 485-93.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1988):
Color for Philosophers.
Hackett.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1988):
Phenomenal colors and sorites.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 22, pp. 213-34.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1989):
Could white be green?.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 390, pp. 285-8.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1989):
Idle colors and busy spectra.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 49, pp. 47-8.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1990):
Color and illusion.
In: W. Lycan (Ed.): 'Mind and Cognition '.
Blackwell.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(1993):
van Brakel and the not-so-naked emperor.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 44, pp. 137-50.

@

Hardin, C. L.

(2004):
A green thought in a green shade.
In: ' 2004 '.

@

Hare, R. M.

(1984):
Supervenience.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 58, pp. 1-16.

@

Harman, G.

(1969):
Linguistic competence and empiricism.
In: S. Hook (Ed.): 'Language and Philosophy '.
New York University Press.

@

Harman, G.

(1973):
Thought.
Princeton University Press.

@

Harman, G.

(1974):
Meaning and semantics.
In: M. Munitz; P. Unger (Ed.): 'Semantics and Philosophy '.
New York University Press.

@

Harman, G.

(1975):
Language, thought, and communication.
In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 7, pp. 270-298.

@

Harman, G.

(1975):
Language, thought, and communication.
In: K. Gunderson (Ed.): 'Language, Mind, and Knowledge '.
University of Minnesota Press.

@

Harman, G.

(1977):
How to use propositions.
In: ' 1977 '.

@

Harman, G.

(1978):
Is there mental representation?.
In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 9.

@

Harman, G.

(1982):
Conceptual role semantics.
In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic ', vol. 28, pp. 242-56.

@

Harman, G.

(1986):
Change in View.
MIT Press.

@

Harman, G.

(1989):
Some philosophical issues in cognitive science.
In: M. Posner (Ed.): 'Foundations of Cognitive Science '.
MIT Press.

@

Harnad, S.

(1982):
Neoconstructivism: A unifying constraint for cognitive science.
In: T. Simon; R. Scholes (Ed.): 'Language, Mind, and Brain '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Harnad, S.

(1989):
Minds, machines and Searle.
In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 1, pp. 5-25.

@

Harnad, S.

(1990):
Lost in the hermeneutical hall of mirrors.
In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 2, pp. 321-27.

@

Harnad, S.

(1990):
The symbol grounding problem.
In: ' Physica D ', vol. 42, pp. 335-346.

@

Harnad, S.

(1991):
Other bodies, other minds: A machine incarnation of an old philosophical problem.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp. 43-54.

@

Harnad, S.

(1991):
Other bodies, other minds: A machine incarnation of an old philosophical problem.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp. 43-54.

@

Harnad, S.

(1992):
Connecting object to symbol in modeling cognition.
In: A. Clark; R. Lutz (Ed.): 'Connectionism in Context '.
Springer-Verlag.

@

Harnad, S.

(1994):
Levels of functional equivalence in reverse bioengineering: The Darwinian Turing test for artificial life .
In: ' Artificial Life ', vol. 1, no. 3.

@

Harnad, S.

(1994):
Computation is just interpretable symbol manipulation; Cognition isn't.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp. 379-90.

@

Harnad, S.

(1999):
Turing on reverse-engineering the mind.
In: ' 1999 '.

@

Harnad, S.

(2002):
Symbol grounding and the origin of language.
In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): 'Computationalism: New Directions '.
MIT Press.

@

Harnad, S.

(2003):
Minds, machines, and Searle 2: What's right and wrong about the Chinese room argument.
In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Harnad, S.

(2003):
Can a machine be conscious? How?.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 10.

@

Harrell, M.

(1996):
Confirmation holism and semantic holism.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 109, pp. 63-101.

@

Harris, E. E.

(1966):
The neural identity thesis and the person.
In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 6, pp. 515-37.

@

Harris, H.

(1995):
Identity.
Oxford University Press.

@

Harris, H.

(1995):
An experimentalist looks at identity.
In: H. Harris (Ed.): 'Identity '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Harrison, P.

(1991):
Do animals feel pain?.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 66, pp. 25-40.

@

Harvey, J.

(1992):
Challenging the obvious: The logic of color concepts.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 21, pp. 277-94.

@

Harvey, J.

(2000):
Colour-dispositionalism and its recent critics.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 61, pp. 137-156.

@

Harzem, P.

(2004):
Behaviorism for new psychology: What was wrong with behaviorism and what is wrong with it now.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 32, pp. 5-12.

@

Hasker, W.

(1982):
Emergentism.
In: ' Religious Studies ', vol. 18, pp. 473-88.

@

Hasker, W.

(1999):
The Emergent Self.
Cornell University Press.

@

Hasker, W.

(1999):
The Emergent Self.
Cornell University Press.

@

Hasker, W.

(2004):
The constitution view of persons: A critique.
In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 44.

@

Hassrick, B.

(1995):
Fred Dretske on the explanatory role of semantic content.
In: ' Conference ', vol. 6, pp. 59-66.

@

Hatfield, G.

(1988):
Neurophilosophy meets psychology: Reduction, autonomy, and empirical constraints.
In: ' Cognitive Neuropsychology ', vol. 5, pp. 723-46.

@

Hatfield, G.

(1989):
Computation, representation and content in noncognitive theories of perception.
In: S. Silvers (Ed.): 'ReRepresentation '.
Kluwer.

@

Hatfield, G.

(1990):
Gibsonian representations and connectionist symbol-processing: prospects for unification.
In: ' Psychological Research ', vol. 52, pp. 243-52.

@

Hatfield, G.

(1991):
Representation and rule-instantiation in connectionist systems.
In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind '.
Kluwer.

@

Hatfield, G.

(1991):
Representation in perception and cognition: Connectionist affordances.
In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Hatfield, G.

(1999):
Mental functions as constraints on neurophysiology: Biology and psychology of vision. In (V. Hardcastle, ed) Where Biology Meets Psychology: Philosophical Essays .
In: ' 1999 '.

@

Hatfield, G.

(2000):
The brain's 'new' science: Psychology, neurophysiology, and constraint.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 67, pp. 388-404.

@

Hatfield, G.

(2002):
Psychology, philosophy, and cognitive science: Reflections on the history and philosophy of experimental psychology .
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 17, pp. 207-232.

@

Hattiangadi, A.

(2003):
Making it implicit: Brandom on rule-following.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 66, pp. 419-31.

@

Hatzimoysis, A.

(2003):
Philosophy and the Emotions.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Hatzimoysis, A.

(2003):
Emotional feelings and intentionalism.
In: A. Hatimoysis (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Emotions '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1978):
The nature and plausibility of cognitivism.
In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences ', vol. 1, pp. 215-26.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1979):
Understanding natural language.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 76, pp. 619-32.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1981):
Semantic engines: An introduction to mind design.
In: J. Haugeland (Ed.): 'Mind Design '.
MIT Press.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1981):
Mind Design.
MIT Press.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1982):
Weak supervenience.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 19, pp. 93-103.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1984):
Ontological supervenience.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement ', vol. 22, pp. 1-12.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1987):
An overview of the frame problem.
In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): 'The Robot's Dilemma '.
Ablex.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1990):
The Intentionality All-Stars.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 4, pp. 383-427.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1993):
Pattern and being.
In: B. Dahlbom (Ed.): 'Dennett and His Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1993):
Mind embodied and embedded.
In: Y. Houng; J. Ho (Ed.): 'Mind and Cognition:1993 International Symposium '.
Academia Sinica.

@

Haugeland, J.

(1993):
Mind embodied and embedded.
In: Y. Houng; J. Ho (Ed.): 'Mind and Cognition:1993 International Symposium '.
Academia Sinica.

@

Haugeland, J.

(2002):
Authentic intentionality.
In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): 'Computationalism: New Directions '.
MIT Press.

@

Haugeland, J.

(2003):
Syntax, semantics, physics.
In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Haugen, D.

(1995):
Personal identity and concern for the future.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 24, pp. 481-492.

@

Haukioja, J.

(2002):
Soames and Zalabardo on Kripke's Wittgenstein.
In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien ', vol. 64, pp. 157-73.

@

Haukioja, J.

(2004):
Is solitary rule-following possible?.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 32.

@

Haukioja, J.

(2006):
Semantic externalism and a priori self-knowledge.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 19.

@

Haukioja, J.

(2006):
Semantic externalism and a priori self-knowledge.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 19.

@

Haukioja, J.

(2006):
Hindriks on rule-following.
In: ' 2006 '.

@

Hauser, L.

(1993):
Reaping the whirlwind: Reply to Harnad's "Other bodies, other minds".
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 3, pp. 219-37.

@

Hauser, L.

(1993):
Why isn't my pocket calculator a thinking thing?.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 3, pp. 3-10.

@

Hauser, L.

(1995):
Natural language and thought: Doing without mentalese.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 23, pp. 41-47.

@

Hauser, L.

(1997):
Searle's Chinese box: Debunking the Chinese room argument.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 7, pp. 199-226.

@

Hauser, L.

(2001):
Look who's moving the goal posts now.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 11, pp. 41-51.

@

Hauser, L.

(2003):
Nixin' goes to China.
In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Hawthorne, J.

(1989):
On the compatibility of connectionist and classical models.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 2, pp. 5-16.

@

Hawthorne, J.

(2002):
Blocking definitions of materialism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 110, pp. 103-13.

@

Haybron, D. M.

(2000):
The causal and explanatory role of information stored in connectionist networks.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 10, pp. 361-380.

@

Haybron, D. M.

(2001):
Happiness and pleasure.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 62, pp. 501-528.

@

Hayes, P.

(1987):
What the frame problem is and isn't.
In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): 'The Robot's Dilemma '.
Ablex.

@

Hayes, P. J.; Ford, K. M.; Adams-Webber, J. R.

(1994):
Human reasoning about artificial intelligence.
In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 4, pp. 247-63.

@

Hayes, P.; Ford, K.

(1995):
Turing test considered harmful.
In: ' <i>Proceedings of the Fourteenth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence</i> ', vol. 1, pp. 972-77.

@

Hayes, P.; Harnad, S.; Perlis, D.; Block, N.

(1992):
Virtual symposium on virtual mind.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 2.

@

Hazen, A. P.

(1999):
On naming the colours.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 77, pp. 224-231.

@

Heal, J.

(1986):
Replication and functionalism.
In: J. Butterfield (Ed.): 'Language, Mind, and Logic '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Heal, J.

(1994):
Semantic holism: Still a good buy.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 68, pp. 325-39.

@

Heal, J.

(1994):
Simulation vs. theory-theory: What is at issue?.
In: C. Peacocke (Ed.): 'Objectivity, Simulation, and the Unity of Consciousness '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Heal, J.

(1995):
How to think about thinking.
In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation '.
Blackwell.

@

Heal, J.

(1996):
Simulation and cognitive penetrability.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp. 44-67.

@

Heal, J.

(1996):
Simulation, theory, and content.
In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Heal, J.

(1997):
Understanding other minds from inside.
In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Heal, J.

(1998):
Externalism and memory.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 72, pp. 77-94.

@

Heal, J.

(1998):
Co-cognition and off-line simulation: Two ways of understanding the simulation approach.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp. 477-498.

@

Heal, J.

(2000):
Other minds, rationality and analogy.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplement ', vol. 74, pp. 1-19.

@

Heal, J.

(2000):
Other minds, rationality, and analogy.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 74, pp. 1-19.

@

Heal, J.

(2000):
Understanding other minds from the inside.
In: ' Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp. 39-55.

@

Heal, J.

(2001):
On first-person authority.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 102, pp. 1-19.

@

Heal, J.

(2003):
Mind, Reason, and Imagination: Selected Essays in Philosophy of Mind and Language.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Heal, J.

(2005):
Joint attention and understanding the mind. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler, eds) Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds .
In: ' 2005 '.

@

Hedman, C. G.

(1970):
On correlating brain states with psychological states.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 48, pp. 247-51.

@

Hedman, C. G.

(1970):
On correlating brain states with psychological states.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 48, pp. 247-51.

@

Heidelberger, H.

(1966):
On characterizing the psychological.
In: ' 1966 '.

@

Heil, J.

(1970):
Sensations, experiences, and brain processes.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 45, pp. 221-6.

@

Heil, J.

(1981):
Does cognitive psychology rest on a mistake?.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 90, pp. 321-42.

@

Heil, J.

(1982):
Speechless brutes.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 42, pp. 400-406.

@

Heil, J.

(1986):
Formalism and psychological explanation.
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 7, pp. 1-10.

@

Heil, J.

(1988):
Privileged access.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 98, pp. 238-51.

@

Heil, J.

(1992):
The Nature of True Minds.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Heil, J.

(1992):
Mentality and causality.
In: ' Topoi ', vol. 11, pp. 103-110.

@

Heil, J.

(1995):
Supervenience redux.
In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Heil, J.

(1999):
Multiple realizability.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 36, pp. 189-208.

@

Heil, J.

(2002):
Mental causation.
In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind '.
Blackwell.

@

Heil, J.

(2003):
Multiply realized properties.
In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation '.
Imprint Academic.

@

Heil, J.

(2004):
Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology.
Oxford University Press.

@

Heil, J.; Martin, C. B.

(1998):
Rules and powers.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 12, pp. 283-312.

@

Heil, J.; Mele, A.

(1991):
Mental causes.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 28, pp. 61-71.

@

Heil, J.; Robb, D.

(2003):
Mental properties.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 40, pp. 175-196.

@

Heinaman, R.

(1986):
Incompatibilism without the principle of alternative possibilities.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 64, pp. 266-76.

@

Heinimaa, M.

(2000):
Ambiguities in the psychiatric use of the concepts of the person: An analysis.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology ', vol. 7, pp. 125-136.

@

Heitner, R.

(2000):
Is design relative or real? Dennett on intentional relativism and physical realism.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 10, pp. 267-83.

@

Heller, M.

(1991):
Indication and what might have been.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 51, pp. 187-91.

@

Heller, M.

(1996):
The mad scientist meets the robot cats: Compatibilism, kinds, and counterexamples.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 56, pp. 333-37.

@

Hellman, G.

(1985):
Determination and logical truth.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 82, pp. 607-16.

@

Hellman, G.

(1992):
Supervenience/determination a two-way street? Yes, but one of the ways is the wrong way!.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 89, pp. 42-47.

@

Hellman, G.; Thomson, F.

(1975):
Physicalism: ontology, determination and reduction.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 72, pp. 551-64.

@

Hellman, G.; Thomson, F.

(1977):
Physicalist materialism.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 11, pp. 309-45.

@

Helm, B. W.

(1994):
The Significance of Emotions.
American Philosophical Quarterly 31:319-31.

@

Hendel, G.

(2001):
Physicalism, nothing buttery, and supervenience.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 14, pp. 252-262.

@

Hendel, G.

(2001):
Supervenience, metaphysical reduction, and metaphysics of properties.
In: ' Southern Journal Of Philosophy ', vol. 39, pp. 99-118.

@

Hendel, G.

(2001):
Realization.
In: ' Critica ', vol. 33, pp. 41-70.

@

Hendel, G.

(2002):
On what does the issue of supervenience and psychophysical dependence depend?.
In: ' Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review ', vol. 41.

@

Henderson, D.

(1996):
Simulation theory versus theory theory: A difference without a difference in explanations.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 34, pp. 65-93.

@

Hendrichs, H.

(1999):
Different roots of human intentionality in mammalian mentality.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 51, pp. 649-668.

@

Hendriks-Jansen, H.

(1996):
Catching Ourselves in the Act: Situated Activity, Interactive Emergence, Evolution, and Human Thought .
MIT Press.

@

Henle, P.

(1942):
The status of emergence.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 39, pp. 486-93.

@

Henley, T. B.

(1990):
Natural problems and artificial intelligence.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 18, pp. 43-55.

@

Herbert, R. T.

(1998):
Dualism/materialism.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 48, pp. 159-75.

@

Hershenov, D.

(2005):
Do dead bodies pose a problem for biological approaches to personal identity?.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 114.

@

Herstein, G. L.

(2005):
Davidson on the impossibility of psychophysical laws.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 145, pp. 45-63.

@

Hess, P.

(1981):
Actions, reasons and Humean causes.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 41, pp. 77-81.

@

Hilbert, D. R.

(1987):
Color and Color Perception: A Study in Anthropocentric Realism.
CSLI Press.

@

Hilbert, D. R.

(1992):
What is color vision?.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 68, pp. 351-70.

@

Hiley, D. R.

(1978):
Is eliminative materialism materialistic?.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 38, pp. 325-37.

@

Hiley, D. R.

(1980):
The disappearance theory and the denotation argument.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 37, pp. 307-20.

@

Hill, C.

(2004):
Ouch! An essay on pain.
In: R. Gennaro (Ed.): 'Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness: An Anthology '.
John Benjamins.

@

Hill, C. S.

(1984):
In defense of type materialism.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 59, pp. 295-320.

@

Hill, C. S.

(1984):
Watsonian freedom and the freedom of the will.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 62, pp. 294-98.

@

Hill, C. S.

(1992):
Van Inwagen on the consequence argument.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 52, pp. 49-55.

@

Hillis, D.

(1998):
Can a machine be conscious?.
In: S. Hameroff; A. Kaszniak; A. Scott (Ed.): 'Toward a Science of Consciousness II '.
MIT Press.

@

Himma, K. E.

(2005):
When a problem for all in a problem for none: Substance dualism, physicalism, and the mind-body problem .
In: ' 2005 '.

@

Hindriks, F.

(2004):
A modest solution to the problem of rule-following.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 121, pp. 65-98.

@

Hinton, J. M.

(1967):
Illusions and identity.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 27, pp. 65-76.

@

Hirsch, E.

(1991):
Divided minds.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 1, pp. 3-30.

@

Hirstein, W.

(2004):
Brain Fiction: Self-Deception and the Riddle of Confabulation.
MIT Press.

@

Hobart, R. E.

(1934):
Free will as involving determinism and inconceivable without it.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 43, pp. 1-27.

@

Hobson, J.

(2002):
Sleep and dream suppression following a lateral medullary infarct: A first-person account.
In: ' Consciousness and Cognition ', vol. 11, pp. 377-390.

@

Hockutt, M.

(1967):
In defense of materialism.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 27, pp. 366-85.

@

Hodgson, D.

(1991):
The Mind Matters: Consciousness and Choice in a Quantum World.
Oxford University Press.

@

Hodgson, D.

(2002):
Consciousness, quantum physics, and free will.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Hodgson, D.

(2002):
Physics, consciousness and free will.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Hodgson, D.

(2005):
A plain person's free will. Journal of Consciousness Studies, vol. 12, no. 1, pp. 3-19.

@

Hoerl, C.

(1999):
Memory, amnesia, and the past.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 14, pp. 227-51.

@

Hoerl, C.

(2002):
Reply to 'Neurophysiological evidence for simulation and action'.
In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action '.
John Benjamins.

@

Hoerl, C.; McCormack, T

(2001):
Time and Memory: Philosophical Perspectives.
Oxford University Press.

@

Hoerl, C.; McCormack, T.

(2005):
Joint reminiscing as attention to the past. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler, eds) Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds .
In: ' 2005 '.

@

Hoffman, C. A.

(1993):
Desires and the desirable.
In: ' Philosophical Forum ', vol. 25, pp. 19-32.

@

Hoffman, P.

(1985):
Kripke on private language.
In: ' Philosophical Studies: ', vol. 47, pp. 23-28.

@

Hoffman, R.

(1960):
The problem of other minds - genuine or pseudo?.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 20, pp. 503-512.

@

Hoffman, R.

(1967):
Malcolm and Smart on brain-mind identity.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 42.

@

Hofstadter, D. R.

(1979):
Godel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid.
Basic Books.

@

Hofstadter, D. R.

(1981):
A coffee-house conversation on the Turing test.
In: ' 1981 '.

@

Hofstadter, D. R.

(1981):
Reflections on Searle.
In: D. Hofstadter; D. Dennett (Ed.): 'The Mind's I '.
, pp.

@

Hofstadter, D. R.

(1983):
Artificial intelligence: Subcognition as computation.
In: F. Machlup (Ed.): 'The Study of Information: Interdisciplinary Messages '.
Wiley.

@

Hogan, M.

(1994):
What is wrong with an atomistic account of mental representation.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 100, pp. 307-27.

@

Hohwy, J.

(2001):
Semantic primitivism and normativity.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 14, pp. 1-17.

@

Hohwy, J.

(2002):
Privileged self-knowledge and externalism: A contextualist approach.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 83, pp. 235-52.

@

Hohwy, J.

(2003):
A reduction of Kripke-Wittgenstein's objections to dispositionalism about meaning.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 13, pp. 257-68.

@

Hohwy, J.; Rosenberg, R.

(2005):
Unusual experiences, reality testing and delusions of alien control.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 20.

@

Holland, O.; Goodman, R.

(2003):
Robots with internal models: A route to machine consciousness?.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 10.

@

Holland, R. F.

(1954):
The empiricist theory of memory.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 63, pp. 464-86.

@

Holman, E. L.

(2002):
Color eliminativism and color experience.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quareterly ', vol. 83, pp. 38-56.

@

Holt, L.

(1999):
Rationality is still hard work: Some further notes on the disruptive effects of deliberation.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 12, pp. 215-219.

@

Holtzman, S.; Leich, C.

(1981):
Wittgenstein: To Follow A Rule.
Routledge.

@

Honderich, T.

(1973):
Essays on Freedom of Action.
Routledge and Kegan Paul.

@

Honderich, T.

(1981):
Psychophysical law-like connections and their problems.
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 24, pp. 277-303.

@

Honderich, T.

(1982):
The argument for anomalous monism.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 42, pp. 59-64.

@

Honderich, T.

(1988):
A Theory of Determinism.
Oxford University Press.

@

Honderich, T.

(1993):
The union theory and anti-individualism.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Honderich, T.

(1993):
How Free Are You?.
Oxford University Press.

@

Honderich, T.

(1996):
Compatibilism, incompatibilism, and the smart aleck.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 56, pp. 855-62.

@

Honderich, T.

(2002):
Determinism as true, compatibilism and incompatibilism as false, and the real alternative.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Honderich, T.

(2002):
How Free Are You? The Determinism Problem. Oxford University Press. Honderich, T. 2002. Determinism as true, compatibilism and incompatibilism as both false, and the real problem .
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Hook, S.

(1958):
Determinism and Freedom in the Age of Modern Science.
In: ' 1958 '.

@

Hooker, C. A.

(1975):
The information-processing approach to the brain-mind and its philosophical ramifications.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 36, pp. 1-15.

@

Hooker, C. A.; Christensen, W. D.

(1998):
Towards a new science of the mind: Wide content and the metaphysics of organizational properties in nonlinear dynamic models .
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp. 98-109.

@

Hope, T.

(1994):
Personal Identity and Psychiatric Illness.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 37, pp. 131-143.

@

Horgan, T.

(1981):
Token physicalism, supervenience, and the generality of physics.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 49, pp. 395-413.

@

Horgan, T.

(1982):
Supervenience and microphysics.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 63, pp. 29-43.

@

Horgan, T.

(1984):
Supervenience and cosmic hermeneutics.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement ', vol. 22, pp. 19-38.

@

Horgan, T.

(1984):
Functionalism and token physicalism.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 59, pp. 321-38.

@

Horgan, T.

(1985):
Compatibilism and the consequence argument.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 47, pp. 339-56.

@

Horgan, T.

(1989):
Mental quausation.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 3, pp. 47-74.

@

Horgan, T.

(1991):
Actions, reasons, and the explanatory role of content.
In: B. McLaughlin (Ed.): 'Dretske and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Horgan, T.

(1993):
The austere ideology of folk psychology.
In: ' 1993 '.

@

Horgan, T.

(1993):
From supervenience to superdupervenience: Meeting the demands of a material world.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 102, pp. 555-86.

@

Horgan, T.

(1993):
Nonreductive materialism and the explanatory autonomy of psychology.
In: S. Wagner; R. Warner (Ed.): 'Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal '.
University of Notre Dame Press.

@

Horgan, T.

(1994):
Naturalism and intentionality.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 76, pp. 301-26.

@

Horgan, T.

(1994):
Nonreductive materialism.
In: R. Warner; T. Szubka (Ed.): 'The Mind-Body Problem: A Guide to the Current Debate '.
Blackwell.

@

Horgan, T.

(1997):
Kim on mental causation and causal exclusion.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 11, pp. 165-84.

@

Horgan, T.

(1997):
Connectionism and the philosophical foundations of cognitive science.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 28, pp. 1-30.

@

Horgan, T.

(2001):
Causal compatibilism and the exclusion problem.
In: ' Theoria ', vol. 16, pp. 95-116.

@

Horgan, T.; Graham, G.

(1990):
In defense of Southern Fundamentalism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 62, pp. 107-134.

@

Horgan, T.; Henderson, D.

(2005):
What does it take to be a true believer? Against the opulent ideology of eliminative materialism.
In: C. Erneling; D. Johnson (Ed.): 'Mind as a Scientific Object '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1987):
Settling into a new paradigm.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement ', vol. 26, pp. 97-113.

@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1989):
Representation without rules.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 17, pp. 147-74.

@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1990):
Soft laws.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 15.

@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1991):
Structured representations in connectionist systems?.
In: ' 1991 '.

@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1991):
Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind.
Kluwer.

@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1992):
Cognitive systems as dynamic systems.
In: ' Topoi ', vol. 11, pp. 27-43.

@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1992):
Levels of description in nonclassical cognitive science.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 34.

@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1994):
Representations don't need rules: Reply to James Garson.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 9, pp. 1-24.

@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1994):
A nonclassical framework for cognitive science.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 101, pp. 305-45.

@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1996):
Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology.
MIT Press.

@

Horgan, T.; Timmons, M.

(1993):
Metaphysical naturalism, semantic normativity, and meta-semantic irrealism.
In: ' Philosophical Issues ', vol. 4.

@

Horgan, T.; Tye, M.

(1985):
Against the token identity theory.
In: B. McLaughlin; E. LePore (Ed.): 'Action and Events '.
Blackwell.

@

Horgan, T.; Woodward, J.

(1985):
Folk psychology is here to stay.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 94, pp. 197-225.

@

Horgan, T.; and Tienson, J.

(1995):
Connectionism and the commitments of folk psychology.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 9, pp. 127-52.

@

Hornsby, J.

(1981):
Which physical events are mental events?.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 55, pp. 73-92.

@

Hornsby, J.

(1984):
On functionalism, and on Jackson, Pargetter, and Prior on functionalism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 46, pp. 75-96.

@

Hornsby, J.

(1986):
Physicalist thinking and conceptions of behaviour.
In: P. Pettit; J. McDowell (Ed.): 'Subject, Thought, and Context '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Hornsby, J.

(1992):
Physics, biology, and common-sense psychology.
In: D. Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): 'Reduction, Explanation and Realism '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Hornsby, J.

(1993):
Agency and causal explanation.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Hornsby, J.

(2001):
Simple Mindedness: In Defense of Naive Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mind.
Harvard University Press.

@

Horowitz, A.

(1992):
Functional role and intentionality.
In: ' Theoria ', vol. 58, pp. 197-218.

@

Horowitz, A.

(1995):
Putnam, Searle, and externalism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 81, pp. 27-69.

@

Horowitz, A.

(2001):
Contents just are in the head.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 54, pp. 321-344.

@

Horst, S.

(1995):
Eliminativism and the ambiguity of `belief'.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 104, pp. 123-45.

@

Horst, S.

(1996):
Symbols, Computation, and Intentionality: A Critique of the Computational Theory of Mind.
University of California Press.

@

Horst, S.

(1999):
Symbols and computation: A critique of the computational theory of mind.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 9, pp. 347-381.

@

Horsten, L.

(1995):
The Church-Turing thesis and effective mundane procedures.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 5, pp. 1-8.

@

Horwich, P.

(1990):
Wittgenstein and Kripke on the nature of meaning.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 5, pp. 105-121.

@

Hospers, J.

(1950):
Meaning and free will.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 10, pp. 307-30.

@

Houghton, D.

(1997):
Mental content and external representations: internalism, anti-internalism.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 47, pp. 159-77.

@

Houng, Y.

(1990):
Classicism, connectionism and the concept of level.

@

Howard, G. S.

(1993):
Steps toward a science of free will.
In: ' Counseling and Values ', vol. 37, pp. 116-28.

@

Hoy, R. C.

(1980):
Dispositions, logical states, and mental occurrents.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 44, pp. 207-40.

@

Hubin, D. C.

(2003):
Desires, whims, and values.
In: ' Journal of Ethics ', vol. 7, pp. 315-35.

@

Huby, P.

(1967):
The first discovery of the free will issue.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 42, pp. 333-62.

@

Huff, D.

(1981):
Family resemblances and rule-governed behavior.
In: ' Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 4, pp. 1-23.

@

Hulse, D.; Read, C.; Schroeder, T.

(2004):
The impossibility of conscious desire.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 41, pp. 73-80.

@

Hum, D. D.

(1998):
Davidson's identity crisis.
In: ' Dialectica ', vol. 52, pp. 45-61.

@

Humberstone, I. L.

(1987):
Wanting as believing.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 17, pp. 49-62.

@

Humberstone, I. L.

(1992):
Some structural and logical aspects of the notion of supervenience.
In: ' Logical Analysis ', vol. 35, pp. 101-37.

@

Humphrey, J.

(1996):
Kripke's Wittgenstein and the impossibility of private language: The same old story?.
In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research ', vol. 21, pp. 197-207.

@

Humphrey, J.

(1999):
Quine, Kripke's Wittgenstein, simplicity and sceptical solutions.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 37.

@

Humphrey, N.

(2003):
The Inner Eye: Social Intelligence in Evolution.
Oxford University Press.

@

Humphrey, N.

(2003):
The Mind Made Flesh: Essays from the Frontiers of Psychology and Evolution.
Oxford University Press.

@

Humphrey, N.; Dennett, D. C.

(1989):
Speaking for ourselves.
In: ' Raritan ', vol. 9, pp. 68-98.

@

Humphreys, G. W.

(1986):
Information-processing systems which embody computational rules: The connectionist approach.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 1, pp. 201-12.

@

Humphreys, P.

(1996):
Aspects of emergence.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 24, pp. 53-71.

@

Humphreys, P.

(1997):
How properties emerge.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 64, pp. 1-17.

@

Humphreys, P.

(1997):
Emergence, not supervenience.
In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement ', vol. 64, pp. 337-45.

@

Hunter, D.

(2002):
Mind-brain identity and the nature of states.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 79, pp. 366-86.

@

Hunter, J.

(1971):
Some questions about dreaming.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 80, pp. 70-92.

@

Hunter, J.

(1983):
The difference between dreaming and being awake.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 92, pp. 80-93.

@

Hurley, S.

(1998):
Vehicles, contents, conceptual structure and externalism.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 58, pp. 1-6.

@

Hurley, S.

(2003):
Animal action in the space of reasons.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 18, pp. 231-256.

@

Hurley, S. L.

(1998):
Vehicles, contents, conceptual structure, and externalism.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 58, pp. 1-6.

@

Hutchins, E.

(1995):
Cognition in the Wild.
MIT Press.

@

Hutchins, E.

(1995):
Cognition in the Wild.
MIT Press.

@

Huttemann, A.

(2004):
What's Wrong with Microphysicalism.
Routledge.

@

Hutto, D.

(2004):
The limits of spectatorial folk psychology.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 19, pp. 548-73.

@

Hutton, A.

(1976):
This Godel is killing me.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 3, pp. 135-44.

@

Hyland, M. E.

(1995):
Against nomological reductionism in psychology: A response to Robinson.
In: ' New Ideas in Psychology ', vol. 13, pp. 9-11.

@

Hyman, J.

(2003):
Pains and places.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 78, pp. 5-24.

@

Hyslop, A.

(1973):
Criteria and other minds.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 51, pp. 105-14.

@

Hyslop, A.

(1976):
Other minds as theoretical entities.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 54, pp. 158-61.

@

Hyslop, A.

(1979):
A multiple case inference and other minds.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 57, pp. 330-36.

@

Hyslop, A.

(1995):
Other Minds.
Kluwer.

@

Hyslop, A.; Jackson, F. C.

(1972):
The analogical inference to other minds.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 9, pp. 168-76.

@

Ingarden, R.

(2002):
Open systems and consciousness: A philosophical discussion.
In: ' Open Systems & Information Dynamics ', vol. 9, pp. 125-151.

@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1974):
A formal approach to the problem of free will and determinism.
In: ' Theoria ', vol. 24, pp. 9-22.

@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1975):
The incompatibility of free will and determinism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 27, pp. 185-99.

@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1978):
Ability and responsibility.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 87, pp. 201-24.

@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1980):
Compatibilism and the burden of proof.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 40, pp. 98-100.

@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1983):
An Essay on Free Will.
Oxford University Press.

@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1989):
When is the will free?.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 3.

@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1990):
Logic and the free will problem.
In: ' Social Theory and Practice ', vol. 16, pp. 277-90.

@

Inwagen, van P.

(1992):
There is no such thing as addition.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 17, pp. 138-159.

@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1994):
When the will is not free.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 75, pp. 95-113.

@

Inwagen, van, P.

(2000):
Free will remains a mystery.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 14, pp. 1-20.

@

Inwagen, van, P.

(2004):
The self: The incredulous stare articulated.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 17, pp. 478-91.

@

Irani, K. S.; Myers, G.

(1983):
Emotion: Philosophical Studies.
Haven.

@

Irvine, A. D.

(1983):
Lucas, Lewis, and mechanism -- one more time.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 43, pp. 94-98.

@

Israel, D.; Perry, J.

(1990):
What is information?.
In: P. Hanson (Ed.): 'Information, Language and Cognition '.
University of British Columbia Press.

@

Ivet, P.

(2002):
Emotions, revision, and the explanation of emotional action.
In: ' European Review of Philosophy ', vol. 5.

@

Jack, A.

(1994):
Materialism and supervenience.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 72, pp. 426-43.

@

Jackendoff, R.

(1985):
Information is in the mind of the beholder.
In: ' Linguistics and Philosophy ', vol. 8, pp. 23-33.

@

Jackendoff, R.

(1989):
What is a concept, that a person may grasp it?.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 4, pp. 68-102.

@

Jackendoff, R.

(1991):
The problem of reality.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 25, pp. 411-33.

@

Jackman, H.

(1998):
Individualism and interpretation.
In: ' Southwest Philosophy Review ', vol. 14, pp. 31-38.

@

Jackman, H.

(1999):
Moderate holism and the instability thesis.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 36, pp. 361-69.

@

Jackman, H.

(2000):
Belief, rationality, and psychophysical laws.
In: ' Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, Volume 9: Philsophy of Mind '.

@

Jackman, H.

(2003):
Foundationalism, coherentism, and rule-following skepticism.
In: ' International Journal of Philosophical Studies ', vol. 11, pp. 25-41.

@

Jackson, F.

(1994):
Finding the mind in the natural world.
In: R. Casati; B. Smith; S. White (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences '.
Holder-Pichler-Tempsky.

@

Jackson, F.

(1995):
Essentialism, mental properties, and causation.
In: ' 1995 '.

@

Jackson, F.

(1996):
Mental causation.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 105, pp. 377-413.

@

Jackson, F.

(1996):
The primary quality view of color.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 10, pp. 199-219.

@

Jackson, F.

(1998):
Colour, disjunctions, programming.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 58, pp. 86-88.

@

Jackson, F.

(1999):
All that can be at issue in the theory-theory/simulation debate.
In: ' Philosophical Papers ', vol. 28, pp. 77-96.

@

Jackson, F.

(2001):
Locke-ing onto content.
In: D. Walsh (Ed.): 'Evolution, Naturalism and Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Jackson, F.

(2003):
Representation and narrow belief.
In: ' Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp. 99-112.

@

Jackson, F.

(2004):
Why we need A-intensions.
In: ' 2004 '.

@

Jackson, F.; Pargetter, R.

(1987):
An objectivist's guide to subjectivism about color.
In: ' Revue Internationale de Philosophie ', vol. 41.

@

Jackson, F.; Pargetter, R.; Prior, E. W.

(1982):
Functionalism and type-type identity theories.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 42, pp. 209-25.

@

Jackson, F.; Pettit, P.

(1988):
Functionalism and broad content.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 97, pp. 318-400.

@

Jackson, F.; Pettit, P.

(1990):
In defense of folk psychology.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 59, pp. 31-54.

@

Jackson, F.; Pettit, P.

(1990):
Causation and the philosophy of mind.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Supplement ', vol. 50, pp. 195-214.

@

Jackson, F.; Pettit, P.

(1990):
Program explanation: A general perspective.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 50, pp. 107-17.

@

Jackson, F.; and Pettit, P.

(1993):
Some content is narrow.
In: J. Heil and A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Jacob, P.

(1992):
Externalism and mental causation.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 66, pp. 203-19.

@

Jacob, P.

(1993):
Externalism and the explanatory relevance of broad content.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 8.

@

Jacob, P.

(1997):
What Minds Can Do: Intentionality in a Non-intentional World.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Jacob, P.

(2002):
The scope and limit of mental simulation.
In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action '.
John Benjamins.

@

Jacobson, A.

(2003):
Mental representations: What philosophy leaves out and neuroscience puts in.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 16, pp. 189-204.

@

Jacoby, H.

(1985):
Eliminativism, meaning and qualitative states.
In: ' 1985 '.

@

Jacovides, M.

(2000):
Cambridge changes of color.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 81, pp. 142-164.

@

Jacquette, D.

(1985):
Logical behaviorism and the simulation of mental episodes.
In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior ', vol. 6, pp. 325-332.

@

Jacquette, D.

(1987):
Metamathematical criteria for minds and machines.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 27, pp. 1-16.

@

Jacquette, D.

(1989):
Searle's intentionality thesis.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 80, pp. 267-75.

@

Jacquette, D.

(1989):
Adventures in the Chinese Room.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 49, pp. 605-23.

@

Jacquette, D.

(1990):
Intentionality and Stich's theory of brain sentence syntax.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly, ', vol. 40, pp. 169-82.

@

Jacquette, D.

(1990):
Fear and loathing (and other intentional states) in Searle's Chinese Room.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 3, pp. 287-304.

@

Jacquette, D.

(1993):
Who's afraid of the Turing test?.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 20, pp. 63-74.

@

Jacquette, D.

(1993):
A Turing test conversation.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 68, pp. 231-33.

@

Jacquette, D.

(1996):
Lloyd on intrinsic natural representation in simple mechanical minds.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 6, pp. 47-60.

@

Jahren, N.

(1990):
Can semantics be syntactic?.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 82, pp. 309-28.

@

James, W.

(1884):
What is an emotion?.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 19, pp. 188-204.

@

Janlert, L.

(1987):
Modeling change: The frame problem.
In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): 'The Robot's Dilemma '.
Ablex.

@

Jaworksi, W.

(2002):
Multiple-realizability, explanation, and the disjunctive move.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 108, pp. 298-308.

@

Jeannerod, M.; Pacherie, E.

(2004):
Agency, simulation and self-identification.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 19, pp. 113-146.

@

Jessor, R.

(1958):
The problem of reductionism in psychology.
In: ' Psychological Review ', vol. 65, pp. 170-78.

@

Johannson, I.

(2001):
Species and dimensions of pleasure.
In: ' Metaphysica ', vol. 2, no. 2, pp. 39-72.

@

Johnson, K.

(2004):
On the systematicity of the language of thought.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 101, pp. 111-139.

@

Johnson, K.

(2004):
Gold's theorem and cognitive science.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 70.

@

Johnson, M. L.

(1987):
The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason.
University of Chicago Press.

@

Johnson, M. L.

(1995):
Incarnate mind.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 5, pp. 533-45.

@

Johnson-Laird, P.

(1977):
Procedural semantics.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 5, pp. 189-214.

@

Johnson-Laird, P.

(1978):
What's wrong with Grandma's guide to procedural semantics: A reply to Jerry Fodor.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 9, pp. 249-61.

@

Johnston, M.

(1985):
Why having a mind matters.
In: B. McLaughlin; E. LePore (Ed.): 'Action and Events '.
Blackwell.

@

Johnston, M.

(1987):
Human beings.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 84, pp. 59-83.

@

Johnston, M.

(1989):
Fission and the facts.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 3, pp. 369-97.

@

Johnston, M.

(1992):
Reasons and reductionism.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 3, pp. 589-618.

@

Johnston, M.

(1992):
How to speak of the colors.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 68, pp. 221-263.

@

Jones, D. H.

(1972):
Emergent properties, persons, and the mind-body problem.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 10, pp. 423-33.

@

Jones, J. R.

(1950):
Our knowledge of other persons.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 25.

@

Jopling, D. A.

(2000):
Self-Knowledge and the Self.
Routledge.

@

Jorgensen, J.

(1949):
Remarks concerning the concept of mind and the problem of other people's minds.
In: ' 1949 '.

@

Joske, W.

(1960):
Sensations and brain processes: A reply to Professor Smart.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 38, pp. 157-60.

@

Joyce, P.

(2003):
Imagining experiences correctly.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 103, pp. 361-370.

@

Joyce, R.

(2002):
Moral realism and teleosemantics.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 16, pp. 723-31.

@

Judson, L.

(1988):
Russell on memory.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 88, pp. 65-82.

@

Kahneman, D.; Slovic, P.; Tversky, A.

(1982):
Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Kahneman, D.; Tversky, A.

(1979):
On the interpretation of intuitive probability: A reply to Jonathan Cohen.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 7, pp. 409-11.

@

Kalderon, M. E.

(1987):
Epiphenomenalism and content.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 52, pp. 71-90.

@

Kalke, W.

(1969):
What's wrong with Fodor's and Putnam's functionalism.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 3, pp. 83-93.

@

Kane, R.

(1985):
Free Will and Values.
SUNY Press.

@

Kane, R.

(1988):
Libertarianism and rationality revisited.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 26, pp. 441-60.

@

Kane, R.

(1989):
Two kinds of incompatibilism.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 69, pp. 219-54.

@

Kane, R.

(1994):
Free will: The illusive ideal.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 75, pp. 25-60.

@

Kane, R.

(1996):
The Significance of Free Will.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kane, R.

(1996):
Free will, responsibility, and will-setting.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 24, pp. 67-90.

@

Kane, R.

(1999):
Responsibility, luck, and chance: Reflections on free will and determinism.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 96, pp. 217-40.

@

Kane, R.

(2000):
The dual regress of free will and the role of alternative possibilities.
In: ' Philosopical Perspectives ', vol. 14, pp. 57-80.

@

Kane, R.

(2001):
Free Will.
Blackwell.

@

Kane, R.

(2002):
The Oxford Handbook of Free Will.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kane, R.

(2002):
Some neglected pathways in the free will labyrinth.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kane, R.

(2002):
The contours of contemporary free will debates.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kane, R.

(2002):
The Oxford Handbook on Free Will.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kane, R.

(2002):
Some neglected pathways in the free will labyrinth.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kane, R. H.

(1966):
Turing machines and mental reports.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 44, pp. 344-52.

@

Kapitan, T.

(1986):
Deliberation and the presumption of open alternatives.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 40, pp. 230-51.

@

Kapitan, T.

(1991):
Ability and cognition: A defense of compatibilism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 63, pp. 231-43.

@

Kapitan, T.

(1996):
Modal principles in the metaphysics of free will.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 10, pp. 419-45.

@

Kapitan, T.

(2000):
Autonomy and manipulated freedom.
In: ' Philosopical Perspectives ', vol. 14, pp. 81-104.

@

Kapitan, T.

(2002):
A master argument for incompatibilism?.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kapitan, T.

(2002):
A master argument for incompatibilism?.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kaplan, S.; Weaver, M.; French, R. M.

(1990):
Active symbols and internal models: Towards a cognitive connectionism.
In: ' 1990 '.

@

Karelis, C.

(1986):
Reflections on the Turing test.
In: ' Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior ', vol. 16, pp. 161-72.

@

Katz, J.

(1966):
Innate ideas.
In: ' The Philosophy of Language '.

@

Katz, J.

(1990):
The domino theory.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 58, pp. 3-39.

@

Katz, J.

(2000):
Realistic Rationalism.
MIT Press.

@

Kaufman, R.

(1985):
Is the concept of pain incoherent?.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 23, pp. 279-84.

@

Kaye, L. J.

(1993):
Are most of our concepts innate?.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 2, pp. 187-217.

@

Kaye, L. J.

(1994):
The computational account of belief.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 40, pp. 137-53.

@

Kaye, L. J.

(1995):
The languages of thought.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 62, pp. 92-110.

@

Kaye, L. J.

(1995):
A scientific psychologistic foundation for theories of meaning.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 5, pp. 187-206.

@

Kazez, J. R.

(1994):
Computationalism and the causal role of content.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 75, pp. 231-60.

@

Kazez, J. R.

(1995):
Can counterfactuals save mental causation?.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 73, pp. 71-90.

@

Kearns, J. T.

(1997):
Thinking machines: Some fundamental confusions.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 7, pp. 269-87.

@

Keeley, B.

(1999):
Fixing content and function in neurobiological systems: The neuroethology of electroreception.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 14, pp. 395-430.

@

Keeley, B.

(1999):
Fixing content and function in neurobiological systems: The neuroethology of electroreception.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 14, pp. 395-430.

@

Keeley, B.

(2000):
Neuroethology and the philosophy of cognitive science.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 60.

@

Keeley, B.

(2000):
Neuroethology and the philosophy of cognitive science.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 67, pp. 404-418.

@

Keijzer, F. A.

(1998):
Doing without representations which specify what to do.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 11, pp. 269-302.

@

Keijzer, F. A.; Bem, S.

(1996):
Behavioral systems interpreted as autonomous agents and as coupled dynamical systems: A criticism.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 9, pp. 323-46.

@

Kekes, J.

(1966):
Physicalism, the identity theory, and the concept of emergence.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 33, pp. 360-75.

@

Kelly, T.

(2002):
The rationality of belief and other propositional attitudes.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 110, pp. 163-96.

@

Kemmerling, A.

(1999):
How self-knowledge can't be naturalized (some remarks on a proposal by Dretske).
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 95, pp. 311-28.

@

Kenny, A.

(1976):
Will, Freedom, and Power.
Blackwell.

@

Kenny, A.

(1978):
Free Will and Responsibility.
Routledge.

@

Kenyon, T.

(2000):
Indeterminacy and realism.
In: A. Brook; D. Ross; D. Thompson (Ed.): 'Dennett's Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment '.
MIT Press.

@

Kernohan, A.

(1985):
Psychology: Autonomous or anomalous?.
In: ' Dialogue ', vol. 24, pp. 427-42.

@

Kernohan, A.

(1988):
Non-reductive materialism and the spectrum of mind-body identity theories.
In: ' Dialogue ', vol. 27, pp. 475-88.

@

Kernohan, A.

(1990):
Lewis's functionalism and reductive materialism.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 3, pp. 235-46.

@

Khalidi, M. A.

(1995):
Two concepts of concept.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 10, pp. 402-22.

@

Khalidi, M. A.

(2001):
Innateness and domain-specificity.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 105, pp. 191-210.

@

Khalidi, M. A.

(2002):
Nature and nurture in cognition.
In: ' The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 53, pp. 251-272.

@

Killeen, P. R.

(2004):
Minding behavior.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 32, pp. 125-147.

@

Kim, J.

(1966):
On the psycho-physical identity theory.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 3, pp. 227-35.

@

Kim, J.

(1972):
Phenomenal properties, psychophysical laws and the identity theory.
In: ' Monist ', vol. 56, pp. 178-92.

@

Kim, J.

(1978):
Supervenience and nomological incommensurables.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 15, pp. 149-56.

@

Kim, J.

(1979):
Causality, identity and supervenience in the mind-body problem.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 4, pp. 31-49.

@

Kim, J.

(1982):
Psychophysical supervenience.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 41, pp. 51-70.

@

Kim, J.

(1982):
Psychophysical supervenience as a mind-body theory.
In: ' Cognition and Brain Theory ', vol. 5, pp. 129-47.

@

Kim, J.

(1984):
Concepts of supervenience.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 45, pp. 153-76.

@

Kim, J.

(1984):
Supervenience and supervenient causation.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement ', vol. 22, pp. 45-56.

@

Kim, J.

(1984):
Epiphenomenal and supervenient causation.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 9, pp. 257-70.

@

Kim, J.

(1985):
Psychophysical laws.
In: B. McLaughlin; E. LePore (Ed.): 'Action and Events '.
Blackwell.

@

Kim, J.

(1987):
`Strong' and `global' supervenience revisited.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 48, pp. 315-26.

@

Kim, J.

(1988):
Supervenience for multiple domains.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 16, pp. 129-50.

@

Kim, J.

(1989):
The myth of non-reductive materialism.
In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association ', vol. 63, no. 3, pp. 31-47.

@

Kim, J.

(1989):
Mechanism, purpose, and explanatory exclusion.
In: ' <i>Philosophical Perspectives</i> ', vol. 3, pp. 77-108.

@

Kim, J.

(1990):
Explanatory exclusion and the problem of mental causation.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Information, Semantics, and Epistemology '.
Blackwell.

@

Kim, J.

(1991):
Supervenience as a philosophical concept.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 21, pp. 1-27.

@

Kim, J.

(1992):
Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 52, pp. 1-26.

@

Kim, J.

(1992):
The nonreductivist's trouble with mental causation.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kim, J.

(1992):
"Downward causation" in emergentism and nonreductive physicalism.
In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism '.
De Gruyter.

@

Kim, J.

(1992):
The nonreductivist's trouble with mental causation.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kim, J.

(1992):
"Downward causation" in emergentism and nonreductive physicalism.
In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism '.
De Gruyter.

@

Kim, J.

(1993):
Naturalism and semantic normativity.
In: ' Philosophical Issues ', vol. 4.

@

Kim, J.

(1993):
Supervenience and Mind.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Kim, J.

(1993):
Can supervenience and "non-strict laws" save anomalous monism?.
In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Kim, J.

(1993):
Mental causation in a physical world.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Science and Knowledge '.
Ridgeview.

@

Kim, J.

(1994):
`Second-order' properties and mental causation.

@

Kim, J.

(1995):
Mental causation: What? Me worry?.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Content '.
Ridgeview.

@

Kim, J.

(1996):
Philosophy of Mind.
Westview Press.

@

Kim, J.

(1997):
Supervenience, emergence, and realization in the philosophy of mind.
In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind '.
Pittsburgh University Press.

@

Kim, J.

(1997):
Does the problem of mental causation generalize?.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 97, pp. 281-97.

@

Kim, J.

(1999):
Making sense of emergence.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 95, pp. 3-36.

@

Kim, J.

(1999):
Supervenient properties and micro-based concepts: A reply to Noordhof.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 99, pp. 115-118.

@

Kim, J.

(2000):
Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind-Body Problem and Mental Causation.
MIT Press.

@

Kim, J.

(2002):
Horgan's naturalistic metaphysics of mind.
In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien ', vol. 63, pp. 27-52.

@

Kim, J.

(2003):
Chisholm's legacy on intentionality.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 34, pp. 649-662.

@

Kim, J.

(2003):
Lonely souls: Causality and substance dualism.
In: T. O'Connor; D. Robb; (eds (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings '.
Routledge.

@

Kim, J.

(2003):
Blocking causal drainage and other maintenance chores with mental causation.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 67, pp. 151-176.

@

Kim, J.

(2005):
Physicalism, or Something Near Enough.
Princeton University Press.

@

Kim, S.

(2002):
Testing multiple realizability: A discussion of Bechtel and Mundale.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 69, pp. 606-610.

@

Kincaid, H.

(1987):
Supervenience doesn't entail reducibility.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 25, pp. 343-56.

@

Kincaid, H.

(1988):
Supervenience and explanation.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 77, pp. 251-81.

@

Kind, A.

(2001):
Putting the image back in imagination.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 62, pp. 85-110.

@

King, D.

(1996):
Is the human mind a Turing machine?.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 108, pp. 379-89.

@

King, D.

(2001):
Entering the Chinese room with Castaneda's principle (p).
In: ' Philosophy Today ', vol. 45, pp. 168-174.

@

Kirk, R.

(1979):
From physical explicability to full-blooded materialism.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 29, pp. 229-37.

@

Kirk, R.

(1982):
Physicalism, identity, and strict implication.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 24, pp. 131-41.

@

Kirk, R.

(1986):
Mental machinery and Godel.
In: ' 1986 '.

@

Kirk, R.

(1986):
Sentience, causation and some robots.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 64, pp. 308-21.

@

Kirk, R.

(1996):
Strict implication, supervenience, and physicalism.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 74, pp. 244-57.

@

Kirk, R.

(1996):
How physicalists can avoid reductionism.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 108, pp. 157-70.

@

Kirk, R.

(1996):
Physicalism lives.
In: ' Ratio ', vol. 9, pp. 85-89.

@

Kirk, R.

(2001):
Nonreductive physicalism and strict implication.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 79, pp. 544-552.

@

Kirsh, D.

(1987):
Putting a price on cognition.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement ', vol. 26, pp. 119-35.

@

Kirsh, D.

(1990):
When is information explicitly represented?.
In: P. Hanson (Ed.): 'Information, Language and Cognition '.
University of British Columbia Press.

@

Kirsh, D.

(1991):
Today the earwig, tomorrow man?.
In: ' Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 47, pp. 161-184.

@

Kirsh, D.

(1991):
Foundations of AI: The big issues.
In: ' Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 47, pp. 3-30.

@

Kirsh, D.; Maglio, P.

(1995):
On distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic action.
In: ' Cognitive Science ', vol. 18, pp. 513-49.

@

Kistler, M.

(1999):
Multiple realization, reduction and mental properties.
In: ' International Studies in the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 13.

@

Kistler, M.

(2000):
Source and channel in the informational theory of mental content.
In: ' Facta Philosophica ', vol. 2, pp. 213-36.

@

Kitamura, T.

(2002):
What is the self of a robot? On a consciousness architecture for a mobile robot as a model of human consciousness .
In: K. Yasue; M. Jibu; T. Senta (Ed.): 'No Matter, Never Mind '.
John Benjamins.

@

Kitamura, T.; Tahara, T.; Asami, K.

(2000):
How can a robot have consciousness?.
In: ' Advanced Robotics ', vol. 14, pp. 263-275.

@

Kitchener, R. F.

(1977):
Behavior and behaviorism.
In: ' Behaviorism ', vol. 5, pp. 11-68.

@

Kitcher, P. S.

(1980):
How to reduce a functional psychology.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 47, pp. 134-40.

@

Kitcher, P. S.

(1982):
Two versions of the identity theory.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 17, pp. 213-28.

@

Kitcher, P. S.

(1984):
In defense of intentional psychology.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 81, pp. 89-106.

@

Kitcher, P. S.

(1984):
Narrow taxonomy and wide functionalism.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 52, pp. 78-97.

@

Kitcher, P. S.

(1988):
Marr's computational theory of vision.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 55, pp. 1-24.

@

Klagge, J. C.

(1988):
Supervenience: Ontological and ascriptive.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 66, pp. 461-70.

@

Klagge, J. C.

(1989):
Wittgenstein and neuroscience.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 78, pp. 319-43.

@

Klagge, J. C.

(1990):
Davidson's troubles with supervenience.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 85, pp. 339-52.

@

Klagge, J. C.

(1995):
Supervenience: Model theory or metaphysics?.
In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Klee, J.

(1984):
Microdeterminism and concepts of emergence.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 51, pp. 44-63.

@

Klee, R.

(1992):
Anomalous monism, ceteris paribus, and psychological explanation.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 43, pp. 389-403.

@

Klee, R.

(2004):
Why some delusions are necessarily inexplicable beliefs.
In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology ', vol. 11, pp. 25-34.

@

Klein, M.

(1990):
Determinism, blameworthiness, and deprivation.
In: ' 1990 '.

@

Klein, M.

(1996):
Externalism, content, and causation.
In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 96, pp. 159-76.

@

Kliewer, G.

(1998):
Neutral color concepts.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 91, pp. 21-41.

@

Knight, D.

(1997):
A poetics of psychological explanation.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 28, pp. 63-80.

@

Knobe, J.

(2003):
Intentional action in folk psychology: An experimental investigation.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 16, pp. 309-325.

@

Knowles, J.

(1998):
The language of thought and natural language understanding.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 58, pp. 264-272.

@

Knowles, J.

(1999):
Physicalism, teleology and the miraculous coincidence problem.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 49, pp. 164-81.

@

Knowles, J.

(2002):
Is folk psychology different?.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 57, pp. 199-230.

@

Kober, M.

(1998):
Kripkenstein meets the Chinese room: Looking for the place of meaning from a natural point of view .
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 41, pp. 317-332.

@

Kobes, B.

(1989):
Semantics and psychological prototypes.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 70, pp. 1-18.

@

Kobes, B.

(1990):
Individualism and artificial intelligence.
In: ' Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 4, pp. 429-56.

@

Kobes, B.

(1991):
On a model for psycho-neural coevolution.
In: ' Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 19, pp. 1-17.

@

Kobes, B.

(1996):
Mental content and hot self-knowledge.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 24, pp. 71-99.

@

Kobes, B.

(2003):
Mental content and hot self-knowledge.
In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies '.
MIT Press.

@

Koethe, J.

(1992):
And they ain't outside the head either.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 90, pp. 27-53.

@

Kolak, D.

(1993):
The metaphysics and metapsychology of personal identity: Why thought experiments matter in deciding who we are .
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 30, pp. 39-50.

@

Kolak, D.

(1993):
Finding our selves: Identification, identity, and multiple personality.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 6, pp. 363-86.

@

Kolak, D.; Martin, R.

(1987):
Personal identity and causality: Becoming unglued.
In: ' 1987 '.

@

Kolak, D.; Martin, R.

(1991):
Self and Identity: Contemporary Philosophical Issues.
Macmillan.

@

Koons, R.

(2002):
Is hard determinism a form of compatibilism?.
In: ' Philosophical Forum ', vol. 33, pp. 81-99.

@

Korb, K.

(1991):
Searle's AI program.
In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 3, pp. 283-96.

@

Korb, K.

(1998):
The frame problem: An AI fairy tale.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 8, pp. 317-351.

@

Korsgaard, C.

(1989):
Personal identity and the unity of agency: A Kantian response to Parfit.
In: ' Philosophy and Public Affairs ', vol. 18, pp. 103-31.

@

Kosslyn, S. M.

(1980):
Image and Mind.
Harvard University Press.

@

Kosslyn, S. M.

(1981):
The medium and the message in mental imagery: A theory.
In: N. Block (Ed.): 'Imagery '.
MIT Press.

@

Kosslyn, S. M.

(1994):
Image and Brain: The Resolution of the Imagery Debate.
MIT Press.

@

Kosslyn, S. M.; Hatfield, G.

(1984):
Representation without symbol systems.
In: ' Social Research ', vol. 51, pp. 1019-1045.

@

Kosslyn, S. M.; Pinker, S.; Schwartz, S.; Smith, G.

(1979):
On the demystification of mental imagery.
In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences ', vol. 2, pp. 535-81.

@

Kosslyn, S. M.; Pomerantz, J.

(1977):
Imagery, propositions and the form of internal representations.
In: ' Cognitive Psychology ', vol. 9, pp. 52-76.

@

Kovach, A.; De Lancey, C.

(2005):
On emotions and the explanation of behavior.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 39, pp. 106-22.

@

Kraay, K. J.

(2002):
Externalism, memory, and self-knowledge.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 56, pp. 297-317.

@

Kraut, R.

(1992):
The objectivity of color and the color of objectivity.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 3, pp. 265-87.

@

Krebs, V.

(1986):
Objectivity and meaning: Wittgenstein on following rules.
In: ' Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 9, pp. 177-186.

@

Krellenstein, M.

(1987):
A reply to `Parallel computation and the mind-body problem'.
In: ' Cognitive Science ', vol. 11, pp. 155-7.

@

Kremer, M.

(2000):
Wilson on Kripke's Wittgenstein.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 60, pp. 571-584.

@

Kriegel, U.

(2002):
Emotional content.
In: ' Consciousness and Emotion ', vol. 3, pp. 213-230.

@

Kuczynski, J. M.

(1998):
A proof of the partial anomalousness of the mental.
In: ' Southern Journal Of Philosophy ', vol. 36, pp. 491-504.

@

Kugel, P.

(2002):
Computing machines can't be intelligent (...and Turing said so).
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 12, pp. 563-579.

@

Kuhberger, A, Perner, J.; Schulte, M.; Leingruber, R.

(1995):
Choice or no choice: Is the Langer effect evidence against simulation?.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 10, pp. 423-36.

@

Kukla, A.

(1989):
Is AI an empirical science?.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 49, pp. 56-60.

@

Kukla, A.

(1989):
Non-empirical issues in psychology.
In: ' American Psychologist ', vol. 44, pp. 485-94.

@

Kukla, A.

(1994):
Medium AI and experimental science.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 7, pp. 493-5012.

@

Kukla, A.; Kukla, R.

(1989):
Meaning holism and intentional psychology.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 173.

@

Kukla, R.

(1992):
Cognitive models and representation.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 43, pp. 219-32.

@

Kukla, R.

(2000):
How to get an interpretivist committed.
In: ' Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp. 180-221.

@

Kulvicki, J.

(2004):
Isomorphism in information-carrying systems.
In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 85.

@

Kurthen, M. Moskopp, D.; Linke, D. B.; Reuter, B. M.

(1991):
The locked-in syndrome and the behaviorist epistemology of other minds.
In: ' Theoretical Medicine ', vol. 12, pp. 69-79.

@

Kurtzman, H. S.

(1983):
Modern conceptions of memory.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 44, pp. 1-20.

@

Kusch, M.

(2005):
Fodor v. Kripke: Semantic dispositionalism, idealization, and ceteris paribus clauses.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 65, pp. 156-63.

@

Kvart, I.

(1986):
Beliefs and believing.
In: ' Theoria ', vol. 52, pp. 129-45.

@

Laakso, A.; Cottrell, G.

(2000):
Content and cluster analysis: assessing representational similarity in neural systems.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 13, pp. 47-76.

@

Lacey, N.; Lee, M.

(2003):
The epistemological foundations of artificial agents. Minds and Machines 13:339-365. Lee, M. & Lacey, N. 2003. The influence of epistemology on the design of artificial agents .
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 13, pp. 367-395.

@

Lachter, J.; Bever, T.

(1988):
The relation between linguistic structure and associative theories of language learning.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 28, pp. 195-247.

@

Lackey, J.

(2002):
Explanation and mental causation.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 40.

@

Ladd, J.

(1952):
Free will and voluntary action.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 12, pp. 392-405.

@

Lahav, R.

(1991):
Between pre-determinism and arbitrariness: A Bergsonian approach to free will.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 29, pp. 487-99.

@

Lahav, R.

(1992):
The amazing predictive power of folk psychology.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 70, pp. 99-105.

@

Lalor, B. J.

(1997):
It is what you think: intentional potency and anti-individualism.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 10, pp. 165-78.

@

Lalor, B. J.

(1998):
Swampman, etiology, and content.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 36, pp. 215-232.

@

Lamb, J. W.

(1977):
On a proof of incompatibilism.
In: ' Philosophical Review ', vol. 86, pp. 20-35.

@

Lamb, J. W.

(1993):
Evaluative compatibilism and the principle of alternate possibilities.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 90, pp. 517-27.

@

Lance, M.; O'Leary-Hawthorne, J.

(1997):
The Grammar of Meaning.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Landers, S.

(1990):
Wittgenstein, realism, and CLS: Undermining rule scepticism.
In: ' Law and Philosophy ', vol. 9, pp. 177-203.

@

Landesman, C.

(1964):
Dreams: Two types of explanation.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 15, pp. 17-23.

@

Landesman, C.

(1989):
Color and Consciousness: An Essay in Metaphysics.
Temple University Press.

@

Langdon, R.; Coltheart, M.

(2000):
The cognitive neuropsychology of delusions.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 15, pp. 183-216.

@

Langsam, H.

(1995):
Why pains are mental objects.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 6, pp. 303-13.

@

Langsam, H.

(2000):
Why colours do look like dispositions.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 50, pp. 68-75.

@

Langsam, H.

(2001):
Strategy for dualists.
In: ' Metaphilosophy ', vol. 32, pp. 395-418.

@

Langsam, H.

(2001):
Pain, personal identity, and the deep further fact.
In: ' Erkenntnis ', vol. 54, pp. 247-271.

@

Langsam, H.

(2002):
Externalism, self-knowledge, and inner observation.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 80, pp. 42-61.

@

Lanier, J.

(1998):
Three objections to the idea of artificial intelligence.
In: S. Hameroff; A. Kaszniak; A. Scott (Ed.): 'Toward a Science of Consciousness II '.
MIT Press.

@

Larkin, W. S.

(1999):
Brute error with respect to content.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 94, pp. 159-71.

@

Larkin, W. S.

(1999):
Shoemaker on Moore's paradox and self-knowledge.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 96, pp. 239-52.

@

Larmer, R.

(1986):
Mind-body interactionism and the conservation of energy.
In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 26, pp. 277-85.

@

Larson, E.

(1994):
Needs versus desires.
In: ' Dialogue ', vol. 37, pp. 1-10.

@

Latham, N.

(1999):
Davidson and Kim on psychophysical laws.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 118, pp. 121-44.

@

Latham, N.

(2001):
Substance physicalism.
In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Lau, J.

(2002):
Externalism about mental content.
In: ' 2002 '.

@

Laurence, S.; Margolis, E.

(1997):
Regress arguments for the language of thought.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 57, pp. 60-66.

@

Laurence, S.; Margolis, E.

(2001):
The poverty of the stimulus argument.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 52, pp. 217-276.

@

Laurence, S.; Margolis, E.

(2003):
Concepts and conceptual analysis.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 67, pp. 253-282.

@

Laurence, S.; Margolis, E.

(2003):
Radical concept nativism.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 86, pp. 25-55.

@

Lawlor, K.

(2002):
Memory, anaphora, and content preservation.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 109, pp. 97-119.

@

Lawlor, K.

(2003):
Elusive reasons: A problem for first-person authority.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 16, pp. 549-565.

@

Lawlor, K.

(2004):
Reason and the past: The role of rationality in diachronic self-knowledge.
In: ' 2004 '.

@

LeBar, M.

(2001):
Simulation, theory, and emotion.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 14, pp. 423-434.

@

LePore, E.

(1990):
Subjectivism and environmentalism.
In: ' Inquiry ', vol. 33, pp. 197-214.

@

LePore, E.; Loewer, B.

(1986):
Solipsistic semantics.
In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 10, pp. 595-614.

@

LePore, E.; Loewer, B.

(1987):
Mind matters.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 630.

@

LePore, E.; Loewer, B.

(1989):
Dual aspect semantics.
In: S. Silvers (Ed.): 'ReRepresentation '.
Kluwer.

@

LePore, E.; Loewer, B.

(1989):
More on making mind matter.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 17, pp. 175-91.

@

Leder, D.

(1985):
Troubles with token identity.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 47, pp. 79-94.

@

Lee, B.

(2002):
Shoemaker on second-order belief and self-deception.
In: ' Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review ', vol. 41.

@

Lee, E. T.

(1996):
On the Turing test for artificial intelligence.
In: ' Kybernetes ', vol. 25.

@

Lee, W.

(1990):
Personal identity, the temporality of agency, and moral responsibility.
In: ' Auslegung ', vol. 16, pp. 17-29.

@

Legg, C. R.

(1988):
Connectionism and physiological psychology: A marriage made in heaven?.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 1, pp. 263-78.

@

Lehrer, K.

(1964):
'Could' and determinism.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 24, pp. 159-60.

@

Lehrer, K.

(1966):
Freedom and Determinism.
Random House.

@

Lehrer, K.

(1966):
An empirical disproof of determinism.
In: K. Lehrer (Ed.): 'Freedom and Determinism '.
Random House.

@

Lehrer, K.

(1976):
'Can' in theory and practice: A possible worlds analysis.
In: M. Brand; D. Walton (Ed.): 'Action Theory '.
Reidel.

@

Lehrer, K.

(1983):
Belief, acceptance, and cognition.
In: H. Parret (Ed.): 'On Believing '.
De Gruyter.

@

Lehrer, K.

(1986):
Metamind: Belief, consciousness and intentionality.
In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): 'Belief: Form, Content, and Function '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Leiber, J.

(1989):
Shanon on the Turing test.
In: ' 1989 '.

@

Leiber, J.

(1995):
On Turing's Turing Test and why the matter matters.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 104, pp. 59-69.

@

Leiber, J.

(2001):
Turing and the fragility and insubstantiality of evolutionary explanations: A puzzle about the unity of Alan Turing's work with some larger implications .
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 14, pp. 83-94.

@

Leiter, B.; Miller, A.

(1994):
Mind doesn't matter yet.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 72, pp. 220-28.

@

Leiter, B.; Miller, A.

(1998):
Closet dualism and mental causation.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 28, pp. 161-181.

@

Lemaire, S.

(2002):
From emotions to desires.
In: ' European Review of Philosophy ', vol. 5, pp. 109-136.

@

Lenman, J.

(1994):
Beliefs about other minds: A pragmatic justification.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 31, pp. 223-34.

@

Leon, M.

(1998):
The unnaturalness of the mental: The status of folk psychology.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 36, pp. 367-92.

@

Leon, M.

(2002):
Colour wars: Dividing the spoils.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 77, pp. 175-192.

@

Leslie, A. M.; German, T. P.

(1995):
Knowledge and ability in "theory of mind": A one-eyed overview of a debate.
In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation '.
Blackwell.

@

Letwin, O.

(1987):
Ethics, Emotion, and the Unity of the Self.
Croom Helm.

@

Levi, I.

(2002):
Commitment and change of view.
In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature '.
Clarendon.

@

Levin, J.

(1995):
Folk psychology and the simulationist challenge.
In: ' Acta Analytica ', vol. 10, pp. 77-100.

@

Levin, J.

(2000):
Dispositional theories of color and the claims of common sense.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 100, pp. 151-174.

@

Levin, M.

(1984):
Why we believe in other minds.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 44, pp. 343-59.

@

Levine, A.; Bickhard, MH.

(1999):
Concepts: Where Fodor went wrong.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 12, pp. 5-23.

@

Levine, J.

(1996):
Swampjoe: mind or simulation?.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp. 86-91.

@

Levy, D.

(2003):
Neural holism and free will.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 16, pp. 205-229.

@

Levy, K.

(2001):
The main problem with USC libertarianism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 105, pp. 107-127.

@

Levy, N.

(2004):
Evolutionary psychology, human universals, and the standard social science model.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 19, pp. 459-72.

@

Lewis, A.

(1988):
Wittgenstein and rule-scepticism.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 38, pp. 280-304.

@

Lewis, D.

(1965):
An argument for the identity theory.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 63, pp. 17-25.

@

Lewis, D.

(1966):
An argument for the identity theory.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 63, pp. 17-25.

@

Lewis, D.

(1969):
Lucas against mechanism.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 44, pp. 231-3.

@

Lewis, D.

(1972):
Psychophysical and theoretical identifications.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 50, pp. 249-58.

@

Lewis, D.

(1972):
Psychophysical and theoretical identifications.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 50, pp. 249-58.

@

Lewis, D.

(1976):
Survival and identity.
In: A. Rorty (Ed.): 'The Identities of Persons '.
University of California Press.

@

Lewis, D.

(1978):
Mad pain and martian pain.
In: N. Block (Ed.): 'Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology '.
, Vol.

@

Lewis, D.

(1979):
Lucas against mechanism II.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 9, pp. 373-6.

@

Lewis, D.

(1981):
Are we free to break the laws?.
In: ' Theoria ', vol. 47, pp. 113-21.

@

Lewis, D.

(1983):
New work for a theory of universals.
In: ' 1983 '.

@

Lewis, D.

(1988):
Desire as belief.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 97, pp. 323-32.

@

Lewis, D.

(1996):
Desire as belief II.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 105, pp. 303-13.

@

Lewis, D.

(1997):
Naming the colours.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 75, pp. 325-42.

@

Lewis, H.

(1985):
Is the mental supervenient on the physical?.
In: B. Vermazen; M. Hintikka (Ed.): 'Essays on Davidson '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Libet, B.

(1999):
Do we have free will?.
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 6, pp. 47-57.

@

Libet, B.

(2001):
Consciousness, free action and the brain: Commentary on John Searle's article (with reply from Searle) .
In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 8, pp. 59-65.

@

Libet, B.

(2002):
Do we have free will?.
In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Libet, B.; Freeman, A.; Sutherland, K.

(1999):
The Volitional Brain: Towards a Neuroscience of Free Will.
Imprint Academic.

@

Lidz, J.; Waxman, S.

(2004):
Reaffirming the poverty of the stimulus argument: A reply to the replies.
In: ' Cognition ', vol. 93, pp. 157-165.

@

Litch, M.

(1997):
Computation, connectionism and modelling the mind.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 10, pp. 357-364.

@

Livet, P.

(2002):
Emotions, revision, and the explanation of actions.
In: ' European Review of Philosophy ', vol. 5, pp. 93-108.

@

Livingston, K. R.

(1989):
Concepts, categories, and epistemology.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 19, pp. 265-300.

@

Liz, M.

(2003):
Intentional states: Individuation, explanation, and supervenience.
In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind '.
CSLI.

@

Lizza, J. P.

(1993):
Multiple personality and personal identity revisited.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 44, pp. 263-274.

@

Lloyd, D.

(1987):
Mental representation from the bottom up.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 70, pp. 23-78.

@

Lloyd, D.

(1989):
Parallel distributed processing and cognition: Only connect?.
In: ' Simple Minds '.

@

Lloyd, D.

(1989):
Simple Minds.
MIT Press.

@

Lloyd, D.

(2000):
Terra cognita: From functional neuroimaging to the map of the mind.
In: ' Brain and Mind ', vol. 1, pp. 93-116.

@

Lloyd, D.

(2002):
Studying the mind from the inside out.
In: ' Brain and Mind ', vol. 3, pp. 243-59.

@

Lloyd, E.

(2004):
Kanzi, evolution, and language.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 19, pp. 577-88.

@

Lloyd, E. A.

(1999):
Evolutionary psychology: The burdens or proof.
In: ' Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 14, pp. 211-33.

@

Loar, B.

(1982):
Must beliefs be sentences?.
In: ' 1982 '.

@

Loar, B.

(1982):
Conceptual role and truth conditions.
In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic ', vol. 23, pp. 272-83.

@

Loar, B.

(1987):
Social content and psychological content.
In: R. Grimm; D. Merrill (Ed.): 'Contents of Thought '.
University of Arizona Press.

@

Loar, B.

(1987):
Subjective intentionality.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 15, pp. 89-124.

@

Loar, B.

(1991):
Can we explain intentionality?.
In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics '.
Blackwell.

@

Loar, B.

(1992):
Elimination versus nonreductive physicalism.
In: D. Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): 'Reduction, Explanation and Realism '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Loar, B.

(1993):
Can we confirm supervenient properties?.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Naturalism and Normativity '.
Ridgeview.

@

Locke, D.

(1968):
Myself and Others: A Study in our Knowledge of Minds.
Oxford University Press.

@

Locke, D.

(1971):
Must a materialist pretend he's anaesthetized?.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 49, pp. 217-31.

@

Locke, D.

(1971):
Memory.
Macmillan.

@

Locke, D.

(1973):
Just what is wrong with the argument from analogy?.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 51, pp. 153-56.

@

Locke, D.

(1975):
Three concepts of free action.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 75, pp. 95-112.

@

Lockie, R.

(2003):
Transcendental arguments against eliminativism.
In: ' The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 54, pp. 569-589.

@

Lockwood, M.

(1984):
Einstein and the identity theory.
In: ' 1984 '.

@

Loeffler, R.

(2005):
Normative phenomenalism: On Robert Brandom's practice-based explanation of meaning.
In: ' European Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 13, pp. 32-69.

@

Loewer B.

(1982):
The role of `Conceptual role semantics'.
In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic ', vol. 23, pp. 305-15.

@

Loewer, B.

(1987):
From information to intentionality.
In: ' 1987 '.

@

Loewer, B.

(1995):
An argument for strong supervenience.
In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Loewer, B.

(1996):
Freedom from physics: Quantum mechanics and free will.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 24, pp. 91-112.

@

Loewer, B.

(2001):
From physics to physicalism.
In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Longworth, G.

(2003):
Where should we look for the mind?.
In: ' Think ', vol. 5.

@

Loren, L. A.; Dietrich, E.

(1997):
Merleau-Ponty, embodied cognition, and the problem of intentionality.
In: ' Cybernetics and Systems ', vol. 28, pp. 345-58.

@

Lormand, E.

(1985):
Toward a theory of moods.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 47, pp. 385-407.

@

Lormand, E.

(1990):
Framing the frame problem.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 82, pp. 353-74.

@

Lormand, E.

(1994):
The holorobophobe's dilemma.
In: K. Ford; Z. Pylylshyn (Ed.): 'The Robot's Dilemma Revisited '.
Ablex.

@

Lormand, E.

(1996):
How to be a meaning holist.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 93, pp. 51-73.

@

Losonsky, M.

(1995):
Emdedded systems vs. individualism.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 5, pp. 357-71.

@

Losonsky, M.

(1995):
Emdedded systems vs. individualism.
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 5, pp. 357-71.

@

Lovejoy, A. O.

(1927):
The meanings of "emergence" and its modes.
In: E. S. Brightman (Ed.): 'Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Philosophy '.
Longmans, Green, and Co.

@

Lowe, E.

(2001):
Event causation and agent causation.
In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien ', vol. 61, pp. 1-20.

@

Lowe, E.

(2002):
The rational and the real: Some doubts about the programme of 'Rational analysis'.
In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature '.
Clarendon.

@

Lowe, E. J.

(1991):
Real selves: Persons as a substantial kind.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 29, pp. 87-107.

@

Lowe, E. J.

(1992):
The problem of psychophysical causation.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 70, pp. 263-76.

@

Lowe, E. J.

(1993):
The causal autonomy of the mental.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 102, pp. 629-44.

@

Lowe, E. J.

(2000):
Causal closure principles and emergentism.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 75, pp. 571-586.

@

Lowe, E. J.

(2000):
An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Lowe, E. J.

(2003):
Physical causal closure and the invisibility of mental causation.
In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation '.
Imprint Academic.

@

Lowry, A.

(1974):
A note on emergence.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 83, pp. 276-77.

@

Lubow, N.

(1978):
Mind-body identity and irreducible properties.
In: ' Philosophy Research Archives ', vol. 4.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1961):
Minds, machines and Godel.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 36, pp. 112-127.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1967):
Human and machine logic: a rejoinder.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 19, pp. 155-6.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1968):
Satan stultified: A rejoinder to Paul Benacerraf.
In: ' Monist ', vol. 52, pp. 145-58.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1970):
The Freedom of the Will.
Oxford University Press.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1970):
Mechanism: A rejoinder.
In: ' Philosophy ', vol. 45, pp. 149-51.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1970):
The Freedom of the Will.
Oxford University Press.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1971):
Metamathematics and the philosophy of mind: A rejoinder.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 38, pp. 310-13.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1976):
This Godel is killing me: A rejoinder.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 6, pp. 145-8.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1984):
Lucas against mechanism II: A rejoinder.
In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 14, pp. 189-91.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1994):
A view of one's own (conscious machines).
In: ' Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, Series A ', vol. 349, pp. 147-52.

@

Lucas, J. R.

(1996):
Mind, machines and Godel: A retrospect.
In: P. Millican; A. Clark (Ed.): 'Machines and Thought '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Luce, D. R.

(1966):
Mind-body identity and psycho-physical correlation.
In: ' Philosophy of Science ', vol. 17, pp. 1-7.

@

Ludlow, P.

(1995):
Externalism, self-knowledge, and the prevalence of slow-switching.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 55, pp. 45-49.

@

Ludlow, P.

(1995):
Social externalism, self-knowledge, and memory.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 55, pp. 157-59.

@

Ludlow, P.

(1995):
Social externalism and memory: A problem?.
In: ' Acta Analytica ', vol. 10, pp. 69-76.

@

Ludlow, P.

(1997):
On the relevance of slow switching.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 57, pp. 285-86.

@

Ludlow, P.; Martin, N.

(1998):
Externalism and Self-Knowledge.
CSLI.

@

Ludwig, K.

(1993):
Externalism, naturalism, and method.
In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Naturalism and Normativity '.
Ridgeview.

@

Ludwig, K.

(1993):
Causal relevance and thought content.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 44, pp. 334-53.

@

Ludwig, K.

(1996):
Duplicating thoughts.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp. 92-102.

@

Ludwig, P.

(2002):
Reply to 'Can 'radical' simulation theories explain psychological concept acquisition?' In (J. Dokic & J. Proust, eds) Simulation and Knowledge of Action .
In: ' 2002 '.

@

Lurie, Y.

(1978):
Correlating brain states with psychological phenomena.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 56, pp. 135-44.

@

Lycan W. G.

(1999):
Dretske on the mind's awareness of itself.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 95, pp. 125-33.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1974):
Mental states and Putnam's functionalist hypothesis.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 52, pp. 48-62.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1976):
Quine's materialism.
In: ' Philosophia ', vol. 6, pp. 101-30.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1979):
A New Lilliputian argument against machine functionalism.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 35, pp. 279-87.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1981):
Form, function and feel.
In: ' Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 78, pp. 24-50.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1981):
Psychological laws.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 12, pp. 9-38.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1981):
Psychological laws.
In: ' Philosophical Topics ', vol. 12, pp. 9-38.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1982):
Toward a homuncular theory of believing.
In: ' Cognition and Brain Theory ', vol. 4, pp. 139-59.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1983):
The moral of the New Lilliputian argument.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 43, pp. 277-80.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1986):
Tacit belief.
In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): 'Belief: Form, Content, and Function '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1986):
Thoughts about things.
In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): 'The Representation of Knowledge and Belief '.
University of Arizona Press.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1989):
Ideas of representation.
In: Weissbord (Ed.): 'Mind, Value and Culture: Essays in Honor of E. M. Adams '.
Ridgeview.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1990):
Mental content in linguistic form.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 58, pp. 147-54.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1991):
Homuncular functionalism meets PDP.
In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory '.
Lawrence Erlbaum.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1993):
A deductive argument for the representational theory of thinking.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 8, pp. 404-22.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1997):
Folk psychology and its liabilities.
In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind '.
Pittsburgh University Press.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(1998):
Qualitative experience in machines.
In: T. Bynum; J. Moor (Ed.): 'How Computers are Changing Philosophy '.
Blackwell.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(2002):
Dretske's ways of introspecting.
In: B. Gertler (Ed.): 'Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self-Knowledge '.
Ashgate.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(2002):
Mind and Cognition: An Anthology, 2nd edition.
Blackwell.

@

Lycan, W. G.

(2003):
Free will and the burden of proof.
In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Minds and Persons '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Lycan, W. G.; Pappas, G.

(1972):
What is eliminative materialism?.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 50, pp. 149-59.

@

Lynch, M.; Glasgow, J.

(2003):
The impossibility of superdupervenience.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 113, pp. 201-221.

@

Lyngzeidetson, A.

(1990):
Massively parallel distributed processing and a computationalist foundation for cognitive science.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 41.

@

Lyngzeidetson, A. E.; Solomon, M. K.

(1994):
Abstract complexity theory and the mind-machine problem.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 45, pp. 549-54.

@

Lyons, W.

(1978):
Emotions and behavior.
In: ' 1978 '.

@

Lyons, W.

(1980):
Emotion.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Lyons, W.

(1990):
Intentionality and modern philosophical psychology, I. The modern reduction of intentionality.
In: ' Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 3, pp. 247-69.

@

MacDonald, C.

(1999):
Shoemaker on self-knowledge and inner sense.
In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ', vol. 59, pp. 711-38.

@

MacDorman, K. F.

(1997):
How to ground symbols adaptively.
In: S. O'Nuillain; P. McKevitt; E. MacAogain (Ed.): 'Two Sciences of Mind '.
John Benjamins.

@

MacKay, D. M.

(1967):
Freedom of Action in a Mechanistic Universe.
Cambridge University Press.

@

MacLennan, B.

(1994):
"Words lie in our way".
In: ' Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp. 421-37.

@

Macdonald, C.

(1989):
Mind-Body Identity Theories.
Routledge.

@

Macdonald, C.

(1990):
Weak externalism and mind-body identity.
In: ' Mind ', vol. 99, pp. 387-404.

@

Macdonald, C.

(1992):
Weak externalism and psychological reduction.
In: D Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): 'Reduction, Explanation and Realism '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Macdonald, C.

(1992):
Psychological type-type reduction via disjunction.
In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 30, pp. 65-69.

@

Macdonald, C.

(1995):
Externalism and first-person authority.
In: ' Synthese ', vol. 104, pp. 99-122.

@

Macdonald, C.

(1995):
Psychophysical supervenience, dependency, and reduction.
In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Macdonald, C.

(1995):
Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation.
Blackwell.

@

Macdonald, C.

(1998):
Externalism and authoritative self-knowledge.
In: C. Wright; P. Smith; C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Macdonald, C.

(1998):
Externalism and norms.
In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind '.
Cambridge University Press.

@

Macdonald, C.

(2002):
Theories of mind and 'The commonsense view'. Mind and Language 17:467-488. Maibom, H. 2003. The mindreader and the scientist .
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 18, pp. 296-315.

@

Macdonald, C.; Macdonald, G.

(1986):
Mental causes and explanation of action.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 36, pp. 145-58.

@

Macdonald, C.; Macdonald, G.

(1991):
Mental causation and nonreductive monism.
In: ' Analysis ', vol. 51, pp. 23-32.

@

Macdonald, C.; Macdonald, G.

(1995):
How to be psychologically relevant.
In: C. Macdonald; G. Macdonald (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Psychology: Debates on Psychological Explanation '.
Oxford University Press.

@

Macdonald, C.; Smith, P.; Wright, C.

(1998):
Knowing Our Own Minds: Essays in Self-Knowledge.
Oxford University Press.

@

Macdonald, G.

(1989):
Biology and representation.
In: ' Mind and Language ', vol. 4, pp. 186-200.

@

Macdonald, G.

(1992):
The nature of naturalism.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 66, pp. 225-44.

@

Mace, C. A.

(1949):
Some implications of analytical behaviourism.
In: ' 1949 '.

@

Mace, C. A.

(1949):
Causal laws in psychology.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 23, pp. 61-68.

@

Machamer, P.; McLaughlin, P.; Grush, R.

(2001):
Theory and Method in the Neurosciences.
University of Pittsburgh Press.

@

Machina, K.

(1994):
Challenges for compatibilism.
In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 31, pp. 213-22.

@

Mackay, D. M.

(1951):
Mind-life behavior in artifacts.
In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science ', vol. 2, pp. 105-21.

@

Mackay, D. M.

(1952):
Mentality in machines.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 26, pp. 61-86.

@

Mackenzie, W. L.

(1926):
The notion of emergence.
In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 6, pp. 56-68.

@

Mackie, D.

(1999):
Animalism vs. Lockeanism: No contest.
In: ' Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 49, pp. 369-76.

@

Mackie, D.

(1999):
Personal identity and dead people.
In: ' Philosophical Studies ', vol. 95, pp. 219-42.

@

Mackie, J. L.

(1963):
Are there any incorrigible empirical statements?.
In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 41, pp. 12-28.

@

Mackie, P.

(2003):
Fatalism, incompatibilism, and the power to do otherwise.
In: ' Nous ', vol. 37, pp. 672-689.

@

Maclachlan, D. L. C.

(1993):
Strawson and the argument for other minds.
In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research ', vol. 18, pp. 149-157.

@

Maclennan, B.

(2003):
Transcending Turing computability.
In: ' Minds and Machine